cypherpunks
Threads by month
- ----- 2025 -----
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2024 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2023 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2022 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2021 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2020 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2019 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2018 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2017 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2016 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2015 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2014 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
- June
- May
- April
- March
- February
- January
- ----- 2013 -----
- December
- November
- October
- September
- August
- July
September 2022
- 12 participants
- 419 discussions
“Eleven cases!” Cuomo told me. “The attorney general stands up and says,
‘11 cases of sexual harassment.’ Well, that creates a whole press frenzy.
You don’t even have to bother to read the report. Even if they got a few
wrong, there were so many! What Democrat is going to say anything other
than, ‘You have to resign?’ ”
https://www.nydailynews.com/opinion/ny-oped-reassessing-cuomo-one-year-late…
1
0

United States Supreme Court Preview: The Supreme Court Poised To Address Key Federal Wire Fraud Issue
by Gunnar Larson 06 Sep '22
by Gunnar Larson 06 Sep '22
06 Sep '22
Sounds like Twitter to me:
https://www.mondaq.com/unitedstates/white-collar-crime-anti-corruption-frau…
In the 2022-2023 term, the Supreme Court will address the definition of
"property" under the federal wire fraud statute, which prohibits a person
from "obtaining money or property by means of false pretenses." 18 U.S.C. §
1343. The definition of "property" for the purposes of this statute has
been much debated—need "property" be economic in nature? Must it be
tangible? Can one's admission
<https://www.law360.com/articles/1331758/attachments/0> to a university
constitute "property"? Now, the Supreme Court may answer some of these
questions in *Ciminelli v. United States* (Docket No. 21-1170).1
Mr. Ciminelli was convicted of wire fraud in connection with a bid-rigging
scheme in the "Buffalo Billion" program, an economic development initiative
in Buffalo, New York. The program was facilitated by Fort Schuyler, a
nonprofit entity affiliated with the SUNY system, which issued requests for
proposals ("RFPs") to solicit and accept bids for each project. The
government argued that Mr. Ciminelli and others rigged this process by
secretly tailoring certain RFPs to favor their companies on projects worth
$750 million.
1
0
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Issues_in_anarchism
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Talk:Issues_in_anarchism
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Talk:Issues_in_anarchism/Archive_1
Issues in anarchism
>From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
Part of a series on
Anarchism
"Circle-A" anarchy symbol
History
Outline
Schools of thought
Feminist
Green
Naturist
Primitivist
Social ecology
Total liberation
Individualist
Egoist
Existentialist
Free-market
Philosophical
Mutualism
Postcolonial
African
Black
Queer
Religious
Christian
Jewish
Social
Collectivist
Parecon
Communist
Magonism
Without adjectives
Methodology
Agorism
Illegalism
Insurrectionary
Communization
Expropriative
Pacifist
Platformism
Especifismo
Relationship
Syndicalist
Synthesis
Theory
Practice
Anarchy
Anarchist Black Cross
Anarchist criminology
Anationalism
Anti-authoritarianism
Anti-capitalism
Anti-militarism
Affinity group
Autonomous social center
Black bloc
Classless society
Class struggle
Consensus democracy
Conscientious objector
Critique of work
Decentralization
Deep ecology
Direct action
Direct democracy
Free association
Free love
Freethought
Horizontalidad
Individualism
Isocracy
Law
Mutual aid
Participatory politics
Permanent autonomous zone
Prefigurative politics
Proletarian internationalism
Propaganda of the deed
Refusal of work
Revolution
Rewilding
Security culture
Self-ownership
Social ecology
Sociocracy
Somatherapy
Spontaneous order
Squatting
Temporary autonomous zone
Union of egoists
People
Armand
Bakunin
Berkman
Bonanno
Bookchin
Chomsky
Cleyre
Day
Dixon
Durruti
Ellul
Faure
Feyerabend
Godwin
Goldman
Ferrer
Kropotkin
Landauer
Magón
Makhno
Malatesta
Michel
Most
Proudhon
Rocker
Santillán
Spooner
Stirner
Thoreau
Tolstoy
Tucker
Volin
Ward
Warren
Zerzan
Issues
Animal rights
Capitalism
Criticism
Education
Left-wing
Lifestylism
Love and sex
Marxism
Nationalism
Religion
Violence
History
Paris Commune
Spanish Regional Federation of the IWA
Cantonal rebellion
Hague Congress
International Conference of Rome
Trial of the Thirty
Haymarket affair
May Day
Anarchist Exclusion Act
Congress of Amsterdam
Tragic Week
High Treason Incident
Manifesto of the Sixteen
Individualist anarchism in the United States
1919 United States bombings
Biennio Rosso
German Revolution of 1918–1919
Bavarian Soviet Republic
Kronstadt rebellion
Third Russian Revolution
Makhnovshchina
Amakasu Incident
Escuela Moderna
Individualist anarchism in Europe
Spanish Revolution of 1936
Barcelona May Days
Red inverted triangle
Labadie Collection
May 1968
Provo
LIP
Kate Sharpley Library
Australian Anarchist Centenary
Carnival Against Capital
1999 Seattle WTO protests
Occupy movement
Culture
A las Barricadas
Anarchist bookfair
Anarcho-punk
Arts
Culture jamming
DIY ethic
Films
Freeganism
Glossary
Independent Media Center
The Internationale
Jewish anarchism
Lifestylism
"No gods, no masters"
Popular education
"Property is theft!"
Radical cheerleading
Radical environmentalism
Squatting
Symbolism
Economics
Communization
Cooperative
Cost the limit of price
Economic democracy
Economic secession
General strike
Gift economy
Give-away shop
Market abolitionism
Mutual aid
Participatory economics
Really Really Free Market
Social ownership
Wage slavery
Workers' self-management
By region
Africa
Albania
Algeria
Andorra
Argentina
Armenia
Australia
Austria
Azerbaijan
Bangladesh
Belarus
Belgium
Bolivia
Bosnia and Herzegovina
Brazil
Bulgaria
Canada
Chile
China
Colombia
Costa Rica
Croatia
Cuba
Czech Republic
Denmark
Dominican Republic
East Timor
Ecuador
Egypt
El Salvador
Estonia
Finland
France
French Guiana
Georgia
Germany
Greece
Guatemala
Hong Kong
Hungary
Iceland
India
Indonesia
Iran
Ireland
Israel
Italy
Japan
Korea
Latvia
Malaysia
Mexico
Monaco
Mongolia
Morocco
Netherlands
New Zealand
Nicaragua
Nigeria
Norway
Panama
Paraguay
Peru
Philippines
Poland
Portugal
Puerto Rico
Romania
Russia
Serbia
Singapore
South Africa
Spain
Sweden
Switzerland
Syria
Taiwan
Tunisia
Turkey
Ukraine
United Kingdom
United States
Uruguay
Venezuela
Vietnam
Lists
Anarcho-punk bands
Books
Communities
Fictional characters
Films
Jewish anarchists
Musicians
Periodicals
Related topics
Anti-corporatism
Anti-consumerism
Anti-fascism
Anti-globalization
Anti-statism
Anti-war movement
Autarchism
Autonomism
Communism
Counter-economics
Definition of anarchism and libertarianism
Labour movement
Left communism
Left-libertarianism
Libertarianism
Libertarian Marxism
Libertarian socialism
Marxism
Situationist International
Socialism
Spontaneous order
Voluntaryism
BlackFlagSymbol.svg Anarchism portal
A coloured voting box.svg Politics portal
v
t
e
Anarchism is generally defined as the political philosophy which holds
the state to be undesirable, unnecessary and harmful[1][2] as well as
opposing authority and hierarchical organization in the conduct of
human relations.[3][4][5][6][7][8] Proponents of anarchism, known as
anarchists, advocate stateless societies based on
non-hierarchical[3][9][10] voluntary associations.[11][12] While
anarchism holds the state to be undesirable, unnecessary and
harmful,[13] opposition to the state is not its central or sole
definition.[14] Anarchism can entail opposing authority or hierarchy
in the conduct of all human relations.[15][16][17][18]
Anarchism is often considered a far-left ideology[19] and much of its
economics and legal philosophy reflect anti-authoritarian
interpretations of communism, collectivism, syndicalism, mutualism, or
participatory economics.[20] As anarchism does not offer a fixed body
of doctrine from a single particular worldview,[21] many anarchist
types and traditions exist, not all of which are mutually
exclusive.[22] Anarchist schools of thought can differ fundamentally,
supporting anything from extreme individualism to complete
collectivism.[23] Strains of anarchism have often been divided into
the categories of social and individualist anarchism or similar dual
classifications.[24] Other classifications may add mutualism as a
third category while some consider it part of individualist
anarchism[25][26][27] and others regard it to be part of social
anarchism.[28][29]
There are many philosophical differences among anarchists concerning
questions of ideology, values and strategy. Ideas about how anarchist
societies should work vary considerably, especially with respect to
economics.[30] There are also disagreements about how such a society
might be brought about, with some anarchists being committed to a
strategy of nonviolence while others advocate armed
struggle.[31][32][33][34][35]
Contents
1 Definitional concerns
1.1 Individualist anarchism vs. social anarchism
2 Ends and means
2.1 Participation in statist democracy
2.2 Democracy in anarchism
2.3 Violence and non-violence
2.3.1 Pacifism
2.4 Individualism vs. collectivism
3 Identity politics
3.1 Gender
3.2 Ethnicity
3.3 Religion
4 Capitalism
4.1 Globalization
4.2 Left and right anarchism
5 Nationalism
6 Environment
7 Relations with the left
7.1 Communism
7.2 Marxism
8 See also
9 Explanatory notes
10 References
11 Further reading
12 External links
Definitional concerns
Main article: Definition of anarchism and libertarianism
See also: Anarchist terminology
Anarchist schools of thought encompass not only a range of individual
schools, but also a considerable divergence in the use of some key
terms. Some terms such as socialism have been subject to multiple
definitions and ideological struggle throughout the period of the
development of anarchism. Others such as capitalism are used in
divergent and often contradictory ways by different schools within the
tradition. In addition, the meanings of terms such as mutualism have
changed over time, sometimes without spawning new schools. All of
these terminological difficulties contribute to misunderstandings
within and about anarchism. A central concern is whether the term
anarchism is defined in opposition to hierarchy, authority and the
state, or state and capitalism. Debates over the meaning of the term
emerge from the fact that it refers to both an abstract philosophical
position and to intellectual, political and institutional traditions,
all of which have been fraught with conflict. Some minimal, abstract
definitions encourage the inclusion of figures, movements and
philosophical positions which have historically positioned themselves
outside, or even in opposition to, individuals and traditions that
have identified themselves as anarchist. While opposition to the state
is central, there is a lot of talk among scholars and anarchists on
the matter and various currents perceive anarchism slightly
differently.[citation needed]
While it might be true to say that anarchism is a cluster of political
philosophies opposing authority and hierarchical organization
(including the state, capitalism, nationalism and all associated
institutions) in the conduct of all human relations in favour of a
society based on voluntary association, freedom and decentralisation,
this definition has its own shortcomings as the definition based on
etymology (which is simply a negation of a ruler), or based on
anti-statism (anarchism is much more than that) or even the
anti-authoritarian (which is an a posteriori
concussion).[36][verification needed]
Nonetheless, major elements of the definition of anarchism include the
following:[36]
The will for a non-coercive society.
The rejection of the state apparatus.
The belief that human nature allows humans to exist in or progress
toward such a non-coercive society.
A suggestion on how to act to pursue the ideal of anarchy.
Usages in political circles have varied considerably. In 1894, Richard
T. Ely noted that the term had "already acquired a variety of
meanings". In its most general sense, these included the view that
society is "a living, growing organism, the laws of which are
something different from the laws of individual action".[37] Several
years earlier in 1888, the individualist anarchist Benjamin Tucker
included the full text of a "Socialistic Letter" by Ernest Lesigne in
his essay on "State Socialism and Anarchism". According to Lesigne,
there are two socialisms: "One is dictatorial, the other
libertarian".[38] As an anti-capitalist and libertarian socialist
philosophy, anarchism is placed on the far-left of the political
spectrum[19] and much of its economics and legal philosophy reflect
anti-authoritarian interpretations of left-wing politics such as
communism, collectivism, syndicalism, mutualism, or participatory
economics.[20] As anarchism does not offer a fixed body of doctrine
from a single particular worldview,[21] many anarchist types and
traditions exist and varieties of anarchy diverge widely.[22] As a
result, anarchist schools of thought can differ fundamentally yet
maintain the common tenets of anarchism, supporting anything from
extreme individualism to complete collectivism.[39] Strains of
anarchism have often been divided into the categories of social and
individualist anarchism, or similar dual classifications.[40]
Nonetheless, anti-capitalism is considered a necessary element of
anarchism by most anarchists.[41][42][43]
Individualist anarchism vs. social anarchism
Due to the many anarchist schools of thought, anarchism can be divided
into two or more categories, the most used being individualist
anarchism vs. social anarchism. Other categorizations may include
green anarchism and/or left and right anarchism. Terms like
anarcho-socialism or socialist anarchism can also be used as
synonymous for social anarchism, but this is rejected by most
anarchists since they generally consider themselves socialists of the
libertarian tradition and are seen as unnecessary and confusing when
not used as synonymous for libertarian or stateless socialism
vis-à-vis authoritarian or state socialism.[44][45][46][47] Anarchism
has been historically identified with the socialist and
anti-capitalist movement, with the main divide being between
anti-market anarchists who support some form of decentralised economic
planning and pro-market anarchists who support free-market socialism,
therefore such terms are mainly used by anarcho-capitalism theorists
and scholars who recognize anarcho-capitalism to differentiate between
the two.[48][49][50] For similar reasons, anarchists also reject
categorizations such as left[51] and right anarchism
(anarcho-capitalism and national-anarchism),[52] seeing anarchism as a
libertarian socialist and radical left-wing or far-left ideology.[19]
While most anarcho-capitalists theorists and scholars divide anarchism
into social anarchism vis-à-vis individualist anarchism meaning
socialism vs. capitalism, seeing the two as mutually exclusive
although accepting all anarchist schools of thought under panarchy on
the basis of voluntaryism, anarchist theorists and scholars opposing
to anarcho-capitalism reject this, not seeing them as a struggle
between socialism and capitalism or as mutually exclusive, but instead
as complementary, with their differences mainly being based on the
means to attain anarchy, rather than on their ends, arguing against
certain anarcho-capitalist theorists and scholars who see
individualist anarchism as pro-capitalist and reiterating that
anarchism as a whole is socialist, meaning libertarian and
anti-statist socialism. Many anarcho-communists regard themselves as
radically individualists,[53] seeing anarcho-communism as the best
social system for the realization of individual freedom.[54]
Notwithstanding the name, collectivist anarchism is also seen as a
blend of individualism and collectivism.[55] Anarchism is generally
considered an individualist philosophy, opposing all forms of
authoritarian collectivism, but one which does see the individual or
the community as complementary rather than mutually exclusive, with
anarcho-communism and social anarchism in particular most rejecting
the individualist–collectivist dichotomy. Finally, social anarchism is
a term used in the United States to refer to Murray Bookchin's circle
and its omonymous journal.[56][57]
Schools of thought such as anarcha-feminism, anarcho-pacifism,
anarcho-primitivism, anarcho-transhumanism and green anarchism have
different economic views and can be either part of individualist
anarchism or social anarchism. To differentiate it from individualist
anarchism, anarchists prefer using social anarchism, a term used to
characterize certain strides of anarchism vis-à-vis individualist
anarchism, with the former focusing on the social aspect and generally
being more organisational as well as supporting decentralised economic
planning and the latter focusing on the individual and generally being
more anti-organisational as well as supporting a free-market form of
socialism, respectively, rather than seeing the two categories as
mutually exclusive or as socialism vis-à-vis capitalism, leading to
anarchism without adjectives.[58] Mutualism is seen as the middle or
third category between social anarchism and individualist anarchism,
although it has been considered part of both social anarchism[59][60]
and individualist anarchism.[25][61][62] Pierre-Joseph Proudhon spoke
of social individualism and described mutualism and the freedom it
pursued as the synthesis between communism and property.[63]
>From a materialist perspective, individualist anarchism is the
anarchist form in the pre-capitalist and largely agrarian and
merchantilist capitalism before the Industrial Revolution, during
which individualist anarchism became a form of artisanal and
self-employed socialism, especially in the United States. Instead,
social anarchism is anarchism in an industrial society, being the form
of industrial or proletarian socialism, with post-left anarchy and its
criticism of industrial technology and anti-workerism arising in a
post-industrial society. Some anarchists may see such categorisations
in these terms.[64] Despite their differences, these are all forms of
libertarian socialism. Before socialism became associated in the 20th
century with Marxist–Leninist states and similar forms of
authoritarian and statist socialism, considered by critics as state
capitalism and administrative command economies rather than planned
economies, the word socialism was a broad concept which was aimed at
solving the labour problem through radical changes in the capitalist
economy.[65] This caused issues between traditional anarchists and
anarcho-captalists, whose understanding of socialism is that of the
20th century Marxist–Leninist states and whose school of thought is
generally not recognized as part of anarchism.[66][67][68]
Anarchists such as Luigi Galleani and Errico Malatesta have seen no
contradiction between individualist anarchism and social
anarchism,[69] with the latter especially seeing the issues not
between the two forms of anarchism, but between anarchists and
non-anarchists.[70] Anarchists such as Benjamin Tucker argued that it
was "not Socialist Anarchism against Individualist Anarchism, but of
Communist Socialism against Individualist Socialism".[71] Similarly,
the view of an individualist–socialist divide is contested as
individualist anarchism is largely socialistic.[72][73][74][75][76]
Ends and means
See also: Direct action, Illegalism, and Propaganda of the deed
Among anarchists, there is no consensus on the legitimacy or utility
of violence in revolutionary struggle. For example, Mikhail Bakunin,
Peter Kropotkin, Emma Goldman and Errico Malatesta wrote of violence
as a necessary and sometimes desirable force in revolutionary
settings. At the same time, they denounced acts of individual
terrorism, see Bakunin's "The Program of the International
Brotherhood" (1869)[77] and Malatesta's "Violence as a Social Factor"
(1895). Other anarchists such as Leo Tolstoy and Dorothy Day have been
advocates of pacifism.
Anarchists have often been portrayed as dangerous and violent,
possibly due to a number of high-profile violent actions, including
riots, assassinations, insurrections and terrorism committed by some
anarchists as well as persistently negative media portrayals.[78] Late
19th-century revolutionaries encouraged acts of political violence,
called propaganda of the deed, such as bombings and the assassinations
of heads of state to further anarchism. However, the term originally
referred to exemplary forms of direct action meant to inspire the
masses to revolution and propaganda of the deed may be violent or
nonviolent.
While all anarchists consider antimilitarism (opposition to war) to be
inherent to their philosophy,[79] anarcho-pacifists take this further
by following Tolstoy's belief in pacifism. Although numerous
anarchist-related initiatives have been based on the tactic of
nonviolence (see Earth First! and Food Not Bombs), many anarchists
reject pacifism as an ideology, instead supporting a diversity of
tactics. Authors Ward Churchill (Pacifism as Pathology, 1986) and
Peter Gelderloos (How Nonviolence Protects the State, 2005; "The
Failure of Nonviolence",[80] 2013) have published influential books
critical of pacifist doctrine which they view as ineffectual and
hypocritical. In a 2010 article, author Randall Amster argued for the
development of a "complementarity of tactics" to bridge the pacifist
and more militant aspects of anarchism.
As a result of anarchism's critical view of certain types of private
property, many anarchists see the destruction of property as an
acceptable form of violence or argue that it is not in fact violence
at all. In her widely cited 1912 essay Direct Action, Voltairine de
Cleyre drew on American historical events, including the destroying of
revenue stamps and the Boston Tea Party as a defense of such
activities.[81]
Many anarchists participate in subversive organizations as a means to
undermine the establishment, such as Food Not Bombs, radical labor
unions, alternative media and radical social centers. This is in
accordance with the anarchist ideal that governments are intrinsically
evil and that only by destroying the power of governments can
individual freedoms and liberties be preserved. However, some
anarchist schools in theory adopt the concept of dual power which
means creating the structures for a new anti-authoritarian society in
the shell of the old, hierarchical one.
Participation in statist democracy
See also: Criticisms of electoralism and Voluntaryism
Anarchist street art in Madison, Wisconsin declaring: "Our dreams
cannot fit in their ballot boxes"
While most anarchists firmly oppose voting, or otherwise participating
in the state institution, there are a few that disagree. The prominent
anarchist Pierre-Joseph Proudhon stood for election to the French
Constituent Assembly twice in 1848. In the 1890s, Paul Brousse
developed the concept of libertarian municipalism in Switzerland which
involved participating in local elections.[82] Anarchists have opposed
voting for multiple reasons. Taking part in elections has historically
resulted in radicals becoming part of the system they oppose rather
than ending it.[83][better source needed] Voting acknowledges the
state's legitimacy.[84]
During the 2004 United States presidential election, the anarchist
collective CrimethInc. launched "Don't Just Vote, Get Active", a
campaign promoting the importance of direct action rather than
electoral change. Anarchists in other countries often engage in
similar anti-voting campaigns and advocate a more pragmatic approach,
including voting in referenda.[85] Other prominent anarchists like
Howard Zinn and Noam Chomsky have pledged their support for
progressive candidates such as Ralph Nader.[86] In addition to merely
voting, some anarchists such as Proudhon and more recently Icelandic
activist Smári McCarthy[87] have stood for and won elections to
national legislative bodies. American individualist anarchist Lysander
Spooner argued that voting was a legitimate means of self-defense
against the state and noted that many supporters of the state consider
both voting and abstention to be acknowledgments of the state's
legitimacy.[88] Spooner's essay "No Treason"[89] offers an
individualist anarchist rebuttal to the argument that existing
democratic governments are justified by majority consent.
During the 2014 Scottish independence referendum, there was debate
within anarchist circles about whether to take an abstentionist
position, vote for independence,[90] or to vote to remain in the
United Kingdom, thus anarchists rarely fitted into the easy binary of
Yes/No voters of the referendum,[91] with all seeking to go beyond the
choices offered at the ballot box. There was also a debate about what
Scottish independence would mean for the anarchist movement and social
struggle.[92] Groups like the Anarchist Federation in Scotland (mainly
in Edinburgh and Glasgow) took a critical stance skeptical of the
benefits of Scottish independence.[91][93][94]
Within the United Kingdom, there was considerable debate around the
Brexit vote in 2016. Anarchists are traditionally opposed to the
European Union, yet the vote was seen as one imposed by two factions
of the right-wing.[95] Yet again, there was debate about whether to
vote to Remain in the European Union, abstain (some left communists
argued for abstaining)[96] or vote to Leave since the United Kingdom
government (the Conservative Party) was mostly in favour of remain
while UK Independence Party and far-right parties favoured Leave.
There was also debate within the left amongst anarchists and those who
considered themselves to have a Lexit (Left Exit position).[97] The
victory of the Leave side united anarchists, whether voters or
abstainers, against the racist incidents and rise of right-wing
populism and neo-nationalism which was considered to have happened
following the result of the vote.[98] Many anarchists and
anti-authoritarian leftists argue that Brexit was negative for social
struggles and migrants in particular[99] and considerable efforts were
made to analyze why the Leave result happened.[100]
Democracy in anarchism
For individualist anarchists, "the system of democracy, of majority
decision, is held null and void. Any impingement upon the natural
rights of the person is unjust and a symbol of majority tyranny".[101]
Libertarian municipalist Murray Bookchin criticized individualist
anarchists for opposing democracy[102] and said majority rule is
consistent with anarchism.[103] While preferring the term assembly
rather than democracy, Bookchin has in turn been accused of municipal
statism, i.e. non-anarchism.[104] Later, Bookchin renounced anarchism
to identify himself as an advocate of Communalism.
Violence and non-violence
Main article: Anarchism and violence
Anarchists have often been portrayed as dangerous and violent due
mainly to a number of high-profile violent acts including riots,
assassinations and insurrections involving anarchists. However, the
use of terrorism and assassination is condemned by most anarchist
ideology, although there remains no consensus on the legitimacy or
utility of violence. Some anarchists have opposed coercion while
others have supported it, particularly in the form of violent
revolution on the path to anarchy.[105]
Some anarchists share Leo Tolstoy's Christian anarchist belief in
nonviolence. These anarcho-pacifists advocate nonviolent resistance as
the only method of achieving a truly anarchist revolution. They often
see violence as the basis of government and coercion and argue that as
such violence is illegitimate, no matter who is the target. Some of
Pierre-Joseph Proudhon's French followers even saw strike action as
coercive and refused to take part in such traditional socialist
tactics.
Other anarchists advocate Marshall Rosenberg's Nonviolent
Communication that relates to peoples fundamental needs and feelings
using strategies of requests, observations and empathy yet providing
for the use of protective force while rejecting pacifism as a
compromising strategy of the left that just perpetuates violence.
Other anarchists such as Mikhail Bakunin and Errico Malatesta saw
violence as a necessary and sometimes desirable force. Malatesta took
the view that it is "necessary to destroy with violence, since one
cannot do otherwise, the violence which denies [the means of life and
for development] to the workers" (Umanità Nova, number 125, 6
September 1921).[106]
Between 1894 and 1901, individual anarchists assassinated numerous
heads of state, including:
French President Sadi Carnot (1894)
Empress consort Elisabeth of Austria (1898)
King Umberto I of Italy (1900)
United States President William McKinley (1901)
Such propaganda of the deed was not popular among anarchists and many
in the movement condemned the tactic. President William McKinley's
assassin Leon Czolgosz claimed to be a disciple of Emma Goldman.
Goldman disavowed the act, although she did not condemn Czolgosz's
motivations in doing it. Goldman included in her definition of
anarchism the observation that all governments rest on violence and
this is one of the many reasons they should be opposed. Goldman
herself did not oppose tactics like assassination until she went to
Russia, where she witnessed the violence of the Russian state and the
Red Army. From then on, Goldman condemned the use of terrorism,
especially by the state, but she still supported most other forms of
revolutionary violence throughout her life. In a debate with a
pacifist five years before her death, she countered that "the
organized force used against the followers of Gandhi has finally
forced them to use violence, much to the distress of Gandhi" and
concluded that "as a method of combating the complex social injustices
and inequalities, non-resistance cannot be a decisive factor"
(non-resistance was the term for nonviolence used by Tolstoy and other
early 20th century pacifists). Goldman at this time was an information
officer for the anarchist militias of the Spanish Revolution which
were committed to armed struggle.[107]
Depictions in the press and popular fiction (for example, a malevolent
bomb-throwing anarchist in Joseph Conrad's The Secret Agent) helped
create a lasting public impression that anarchists are violent
terrorists. This perception was enhanced by events such as the
Haymarket riot, where anarchists were blamed for throwing a bomb at
police who came to break up a public meeting in Chicago. More
recently, anarchists have been involved in protests against World
Trade Organization (WTO) and International Monetary Fund (IMF)
meetings across the globe which the media has described as violent or
riots. Traditionally, May Day in London has also been a day of
marching, but in recent years the Metropolitan Police have warned that
a "hardcore of anarchists" are intent on causing violence. Anarchists
often respond that it is the police who initiate violence at these
demonstrations, with anarchists who are otherwise peaceful sometimes
forced to defend themselves. The anarchists involved in such protests
often formed black blocs at these protests and some engaged in
property destruction, vandalism, or in violent conflicts with police,
although others stuck to non-violent principles. Those participating
in black blocs distinguish between violence and property destruction
as they claim that violence is when a person inflicts harm to another
person while property destruction or property damage is not violence,
although it can have indirect harm such as financial harm. Most
anarchists do not consider the destruction of property to be violent
as do most activists who believe in non-violence.
Pacifism
See also: Anarcho-pacifism
Anarchist protesters in Boston opposing state-waged war
Most anarchists consider opposition to militarism to be inherent in
their philosophy. Some anarchists take it further and follow Leo
Tolstoy's belief in non-violence (note that these anarcho-pacifists
are not necessarily Christian anarchists as Tolstoy was), advocating
nonviolent resistance as the only method of achieving a truly
anarchist revolution.
Anarchist literature often portrays war as an activity in which the
state seeks to gain and consolidate power, both domestically and in
foreign lands. Many anarchists subscribe to Randolph Bourne's view
that "war is the health of the state".[108] Anarchists believe that if
they were to support a war, they would be strengthening the
state—indeed, Peter Kropotkin was alienated from other anarchists when
he expressed support for the British[citation needed] in World War
I.[109]
Individualism vs. collectivism
Wiki letter w.svg
This section is missing information about Tucker's and Spooner's
understanding of private property (a product of one's labour) and how
it was understood differently by other anarchists (privately owned
land and means of production). Please expand the section to include
this information. Further details may exist on the talk page. (May
2021)
While some anarchists favour collective property or no property,
others such as some American individualist anarchists like Benjamin
Tucker and Lysander Spooner support a form of private property while
opposing property titles to unused land. Tucker argues that
collectivism in property is absurd: "That there is an entity known as
the community which is the rightful owner of all land, [...] I
maintain that the community is a non-entity, that it has no
existence".[110] He was particularly adamant in his opposition to
communism, even to the point of asserting that those who opposed
private property were not anarchists: "Anarchism is a word without
meaning, unless it includes the liberty of the individual to control
his product or whatever his product has brought him through exchange
in a free market—that is, private property. Whoever denies private
property is of necessity an Archist".[111] Similarly, Albert Meltzer
argued that since individualist anarchists like Tucker promote the
idea of private armies, they actually support a "limited State",
contending that it "is only possible to conceive of Anarchism which is
free, communistic and offering no economic necessity for repression of
countering it".[112] Anarcho-communists reject the criticism, pointing
to the principle of voluntary association that underpins their theory
and differentiates it from state communism.[113] Some individualist
anarchists are willing to recognize such communism as a legitimate
form. Kevin Carson writes that "free market, libertarian communist,
syndicalism, and other kinds of collectivist anarchists must learn to
coexist in peace and mutual respect today, in our fight against the
corporate state, and tomorrow, in the panarchy that is likely to
succeed it".[114]
Some forms of anarcho-communism such as insurrectionary anarchism are
strongly influenced by egoism and radical individualism, believing
anarcho-communism is the best social system for the realisation of
individual freedom.[53] Hence, most anarcho-communists view
anarcho-communism itself as a way of reconciling the opposition
between the individual and society.[54] Furthermore, post-left
anarchists like Bob Black went as far as to argue that "communism is
the final fulfillment of individualism. [...] The apparent
contradiction between individualism and communism rests on a
misunderstanding of both. [...] Subjectivity is also objective: the
individual really is subjective. It is nonsense to speak of
"emphatically prioritizing the social over the individual," [...]. You
may as well speak of prioritizing the chicken over the egg. Anarchy is
a "method of individualization." It aims to combine the greatest
individual development with the greatest communal unity".[115] Max
Baginski has argued that property and the free market are just other
"spooks", what Stirner called to refer mere illusions, or ghosts in
the mind, writing: "Modern Communists are more individualistic than
Stirner. To them, not merely religion, morality, family and State are
spooks, but property also is no more than a spook, in whose name the
individual is enslaved — and how enslaved! [...] Communism thus
creates a basis for the liberty and Eigenheit of the individual. I am
a Communist because I am an Individualist. Fully as heartily the
Communists concur with Stirner when he puts the word take in place of
demand — that leads to the dissolution of property, to expropriation.
Individualism and Communism go hand in hand".[116] Peter Kropotkin
argued that "Communism is the one which guarantees the greatest amount
of individual liberty — provided that the idea that begets the
community be Liberty, Anarchy [...]. Communism guarantees economic
freedom better than any other form of association, because it can
guarantee wellbeing, even luxury, in return for a few hours of work
instead of a day's work".[117] Dielo Truda similarly argued that
"[t]his other society will be libertarian communism, in which social
solidarity and free individuality find their full expression, and in
which these two ideas develop in perfect harmony".[118] In "My
Perspectives" of Willful Disobedience (2: 12), it was argued as such:
"I see the dichotomies made between individualism and communism,
individual revolt and class struggle, the struggle against human
exploitation and the exploitation of nature as false dichotomies and
feel that those who accept them are impoverishing their own critique
and struggle".[119]
The Right to Be Greedy is a book published in 1974 by an American
Situationist collective called For Ourselves: Council for Generalized
Self-Management which Black describes it in its preface as an
"audacious attempt to synthesize a collectivist social vision of
left-wing origin with an individualistic (for lack of a better word)
ethic usually articulated on the right".[120] Its authors say that
"[t]he positive conception of egoism, the perspective of communist
egoism, is the very heart and unity of our theoretical and practical
coherence".[121] The book was highly influenced by the work of Max
Stirner, with Black humorously suggesting that it was a synthesis of
Marxism and Stirner's philosophy which may be called
Marxism–Stirnerism just as he wrote an essay on Groucho-Marxism,[122]
writing in the preface to The Right to be Greedy: "If
Marxism-Stirnerism is conceivable, every orthodoxy prating of freedom
or liberation is called into question, anarchism included. The only
reason to read this book, as its authors would be the first to agree,
is for what you can get out of it".[120]
Although commonly misconcepted, Marxism rejected egalitarianism in the
sense of greater equality between classes, clearly distinguishing it
from the socialist notion of the abolition of classes based on the
division between workers and owners of productive property.[note 1]
Marx and Engels believed that an international proletarian revolution
would bring about a socialist society which would then eventually give
way to a communist stage of social development which would be a
classless, stateless, moneyless, humane society erected on common
ownership. However, Marx's view of classlessness was not the
subordination of society to a universal interest (such as a universal
notion of equality), but it was about the creation of the conditions
that would enable individuals to pursue their true interests and
desires, making his notion of communist society radically
individualistic.[126] Marx was a proponent of two principles, the
first ("To each according to his contribution") applied to socialism
and the second ("From each according to their ability, to each
according to their needs") to an advanced communist society. Although
his position is often confused or conflated with distributive
egalitarianism in which only the goods and services resulting from
production are distributed according to a notional equality, Marx
eschewed the entire concept of equality as abstract and bourgeois in
nature, preferring to focus on more concrete principles such as
opposition to exploitation on materialist grounds and economic
logic.[127] He is a believer in human freedom and human development.
For Marx, the "true realm of freedom" consists in the "development of
human powers as an end in itself".[128] He conceives of a communist
society as one in which "the full and free development of every
individual forms the ruling principle".[129] Marx justified the forms
of equality he did advocate such as the communal ownership and control
of the economy on the grounds that they led to human freedom and human
development rather than simply because they were egalitarian, writing
that in such a society there are "[u]niversally developed individuals,
whose social relations, as their own communal relations, are hence
also subordinated to their own communal control". This communal
control includes "their subordination of their communal, social
productivity as their social wealth".[130]
Identity politics
Gender
See also: Anarcha-feminism and Ecofeminism
Emma Goldman
Anarcha-feminism is a kind of radical feminism that espouses the
belief that patriarchy is a fundamental problem in society, but it was
not explicitly formulated as such until the early 1970s during the
second-wave feminist movement.[131]
Early first-wave feminist Mary Wollstonecraft held proto-anarchist
views and William Godwin is often considered a feminist anarchist
precursor. Early French feminists such as Jenny d'Héricourt and
Juliette Adam also criticised the misogyny in the anarchism of
Pierre-Joseph Proudhon during the 1850s. While most anarchists of the
period did not take these ideas seriously, others such as Florence
Finch Kelly and Moses Harman held gender equality as a topic of
significant importance.[132] Anarcha-feminism garnered further
attention through the work of early 20th-century authors and theorists
including Emma Goldman[133][134] and Voltairine de
Cleyre.[135][136][137]
In the Spanish Civil War, an anarcha-feminist group called Mujeres
Libres organized to defend both anarchist and feminist ideas.[138]
Ethnicity
See also: Black anarchism and Postcolonial anarchism
Black anarchism opposes the existence of a state, capitalism and
subjugation and domination of people of color and favors a
non-hierarchical organization of society.[139][140][141][142]
Theorists include Ashanti Alston, Lorenzo Komboa Ervin and Sam Mbah.
Some of these theorists have had past experiences with the Black
Panther Party and came to anarchism after they became critical of the
Black Panther Party's brand of Marxist–Leninism. Anarchist People of
Color (APOC) was created as a forum for non-white anarchists to
express their thoughts about racial issues within the anarchist
movement, particularly within the United States. Anti-Racist Action is
not an anarchist group, but many anarchists are involved. It focuses
on publicly confronting antisemites, racists, supremacists and others
such as the Ku Klux Klan, neo-Nazi groups and the like.
Most modern and historical anarchists describe themselves as
anti-racists. Many early anarchists, notably Lucy Parsons (a person of
color and formerly an enslaved American), viewed racism as one of many
negative side-effects of capitalism and expected that it would vanish
in a post-capitalist world. However, among modern anarchists
anti-racism plays a more prominent role and racism is typically viewed
as one of several forms of social hierarchy and stratification which
must be destroyed. No anarchist organizations has ever included racism
as part of its platform and many—particularly modern
formations—include explicit anti-racism, with the national-anarchist
movement being rejected as part of anarchism for his perceived racism,
among other reasons. For instance, American anarchists were alone in
opposing racism against Chinese and Mexican workers in the late 19th
century and early 20th century. Since the late 1970s, anarchists have
been involved in fighting the rise of neo-fascist groups. In Germany
and the United Kingdom, some anarchists worked within militant
anti-fascist groups alongside members of the Marxist left. They
advocated directly combating fascists with physical force rather than
relying on the state. Since the late 1990s, a similar tendency has
developed within anarchism in the United States.
Anti-Racist Action is one of the largest grassroots anti-fascist and
anti-racist organizations in North America today and counts many
anarchists among its members. Their tactics, centered around directly
confronting neo-fascist and white-supremacist groups, are considered
controversial both within the anarchist movement (where they are
sometimes portrayed as well-intentioned, but ineffective) and in
mainstream society (where they are often portrayed as violent and
disruptive).
Many anarchists also oppose the concept of race itself, arguing that
it has no biological basis in science and is a social construction
designed to divide the working class and preserve capitalism.
A minority of historically prominent anarchists have been accused of
racism, e.g. Pierre-Joseph Proudhon[143] and Mikhail Bakunin.[144]
Religion
Main article: Anarchism and religion
See also: Buddhist anarchism, Christian anarchism, Islamic anarchism,
and Jewish anarchism
>From Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and Mikhail Bakunin to the Spanish
anarcho-syndicalists, most anarchists have questioned or opposed
organized religion, believing that most organized religions are
hierarchical or authoritarian and more often than not aligned with
contemporary power structures like the state and capital. Nonetheless,
others reconcile anarchism with religion.
Christian anarchists believe that there is no higher authority than
God and oppose earthly authority such as government and established
churches. They believe that Jesus' teachings and the practice of the
early Church were clearly anarchistic. Some of them feel that the
teachings of the Nazarenes and other early groups of followers were
corrupted by contemporary religious views, most notably when
Theodosius I declared Nicene Christianity the official religion of the
Roman Empire. Christian anarchists who follow Jesus' directive to turn
the other cheek are usually strict pacifists, although some believe in
a limited justification of defense, especially defense of others. The
most famous advocate of Christian anarchism was Leo Tolstoy, author of
The Kingdom of God Is Within You, who called for a society based on
compassion, nonviolent principles and freedom. Christian anarchists
tend to form experimental communities (such as the Catholic Worker).
They also occasionally resist taxation.
Buddhist anarchism originated in the influential Chinese anarchist
movement of the 1920s. Taixu, one of the leading thinkers and writers
of this school, was deeply influenced by the work of Christian
anarchists like Tolstoy and by the ancient Chinese well-field system.
In the late 19th century, the Ghadar movement in India (see Har
Dayal), influenced by Buddhist thought and by Swami Dayananda
Saraswati (founder of Arya Samaj), saw anarchism as a way of
propagating the ancient culture of the Arya (not to be confused with
the much later appropriation of Aryan identity by Nazism).[145]
Buddhist anarchism was later revived in the 1960s by writers such as
Gary Snyder; an incarnation of this school of thought was popularized
by Jack Kerouac in his book The Dharma Bums.
With its focus on the environment and equality along with its often
decentralized nature, Neopaganism has led to a number of Neopagan
anarchists. One of the most prominent is Starhawk, who writes
extensively about both spirituality and activism.
Discussing the anarchist movement in Britain in 2002, Adam K. has
argued that it "has an especially ignorant and hegemonistic perception
of the Muslim community" which he attributed to "the [A]nglo-centric
nature of the movement". Quoting the statement that "Islam is an enemy
of all freedom loving people" from an anarchist magazine, he argues
that this is "no different to the bigoted rhetoric of George Bush or
even BNP leader Nick Griffin".[146]
Capitalism
Main article: Anarchism and capitalism
See also: Anarcho-capitalism
Throughout all of its history, anarchism has been defined by its
proponents in opposition to capitalism which they believe can be
maintained only by state violence.[147] Anarchists generally follow
Pierre-Joseph Proudhon in opposing ownership of workplaces by
capitalists and aim to replace wage labor with workers' associations.
These anarchists also agree with Peter Kropotkin's comment that "the
origin of the anarchist inception of society [lies in] the criticism
[...] of the hierarchical organisations and the authoritarian
conceptions of society" rather than in simple opposition to the state
or government.[148] They argue that the wage system is hierarchical
and authoritarian in nature and consequently capitalism cannot be
anarchist.[149] Conversely, anarcho-capitalists generally support wage
labor and oppose workplace democracy which most anarchists support,
claiming that wage labor is voluntary. However, most anarchists argue
that certain capitalist transactions, including wage labor, are not
voluntary and that maintaining the class structure of a capitalist
society requires coercion which violates both anarchist principles and
anarcho-capitalism's non-aggression principle itself.[150] Anarchists
who support wage labor do so as long as the employers and employees
are paid equally for equal hours worked[151] and neither party has
authority over the other. By following this principle, no individual
profits from the labor of another. Those anarchists describe the wages
received in such an employer-employee relationship as the individual
laborer's full product and generally envisione that in such a society
every worker would be self-employed and own their own private means of
production, free to walk away from employment contracts.[152]
Some supporters argue that anarcho-capitalism is a form of
individualist anarchism.[153][154][155] However, most early
individualist anarchists considered themselves "fervent
anti-capitalists [who see] no contradiction between their
individualist stance and their rejection of capitalism".[156] Many
defined themselves as socialists. These early individualist anarchists
defined capitalism in various ways, but it was often discussed in
terms of usury: "There are three forms of usury, interest on money,
rent on land and houses, and profit in exchange. Whoever is in receipt
of any of these is a usurer".[157] Excluding these, they tended to
support free trade, free competition and varying levels of private
property such as mutualism based on occupation and use property
norms.[158][159][160] It is this distinction which has led to the rift
between anarchism and anarcho-capitalism. Historically, anarchists
considered themselves socialists and opposed to capitalism, therefore
anarcho-capitalism is considered by many anarchists today as not being
a form of anarchism.[161]
Furthermore, terms like anarcho-socialism or socialist anarchism are
rejected by most anarchists since they generally consider themselves
socialists of the libertarian tradition, but they are nevertheless
used by anarcho-capitalism theorists and scholars who recognize
anarcho-capitalism to differentiate between the two.[162][49][163]
Ultimately, anarcho-capitalist author Murray Rothbard, who coined the
term itself and developed such philosophy through the 1970s, stated
that individualist anarchism is different from capitalism due to the
individualist anarchists retaining the labor theory of value[164] and
many writers deny that anarcho-capitalism is a form of anarchism at
all,[66][67] or that capitalism itself is compatible with
anarchism.[66][68] seeing it instead as a form of New Right
libertarianism.[66]
Anarchist organisations such as the Confederación Nacional del Trabajo
(Spain) and the Anarchist Federation (Britain and Ireland) generally
take an explicitly anti-capitalist stance. In the 20th century,
several economists began to formulate a form of radical American
libertarianism known as anarcho-capitalism. This has met resistance
from those who hold that capitalism is inherently oppressive or
statist and many anarchists and scholars do not consider
anarcho-capitalism to properly cohere with the spirit, principles, or
history of anarchism.[165] While other anarchists and scholars regard
anarchism as referring only to opposition to the non-privatisation of
all aspects of the state and do consider anarcho-capitalism to be a
form of anarchism,[166] Gary Chartier[167] has joined Kevin
Carson,[168][169] Roderick T. Long,[170][171] Charles W. Johnson,[172]
Sheldon Richman[173][174][175] and Chris Matthew Sciabarra[176] in
maintaining that because of its heritage and its emancipatory goals
and potential radical market anarchism should be seen by its
proponents and by others as part of the socialist tradition and that
market anarchists can and should call themselves socialists, echoing
the language of libertarian socialists like American individualist
anarchists Benjamin Tucker and Lysander Spooner and British Thomas
Hodgskin.[177]
In particular, Chartier has argued that proponents of a genuinely free
market, termed freed market to distinguish them from the common
conception which these left-libertarians (referred to as left-wing
market anarchists[178] or market-oriented left-libertarians)[175]
believe to be riddled with statist and capitalist privileges,[179]
should explicitly reject capitalism and identify with the global
anti-capitalist movement while emphasizing that the abuses the
anti-capitalist movement highlights result from state-tolerated
violence and state-secured privilege rather than from voluntary
cooperation and exchange. Indeed, proponents of this approach strongly
affirm the classical liberal ideas of self-ownership and free markets
while maintaining that taken to their logical conclusions these ideas
support anti-capitalist, anti-corporatist, anti-hierarchical and
pro-labor positions in economics; anti-imperialism in foreign policy;
and thoroughly radical views regarding such cultural issues as gender,
sexuality and race.[180][177]
One major issue and divide between anarchism and anarcho-capitalism
are the terms capitalism and socialism themselves. For
anarcho-capitalists, capitalism means the free market rather than
actually existing capitalism (of which they are critics, arguing that
the problem rests on corporatism and state capitalism, a term coined
by German socialist Wilhelm Liebknecht,[181] but whose concept can be
traced back to anarchists like Mikhail Bakunin[182][183] and Jan
Wacław Machajski,[184][185][186][187] rather than capitalism itself)
as advocated by anti-capitalists[188][189] and socialism is conflated
with state socialism and Marxist–Leninist states. However, the term
socialism originally included any opponent of capitalism, a term
coined in the 18th century to mean a construed political system built
on privileges for the owners of capital.[190][191][192]
Contra anarcho-capitalists, anarchists argue that capitalism
necessarily rests on the state to survive and state capitalism is seen
as the inevitable result of both capitalism and state socialism.
Furthermore, the free market itself for classical economists such as
Adam Smith did not necessarily refer to a market free from government
interference as it is now commonly assumed or how anarcho-capitalists
see it, but rather free from all forms of economic privilege,
monopolies and artificial scarcities, implying that economic rents,
i.e. profits generated from a lack of perfect competition, must be
reduced or eliminated as much as possible through free
competition.[193] While anarcho-capitalists who argue for private
property which supports absentee and landlordism ownership rather than
occupation and use property norms as well as the homestead principle
are considered right-libertarians rather than anarchists (this is due
to anarchism generally viewing any absentee ownership and ownership
claims on land and natural resources as immoral and illegitimate[194]
and seeing the idea of perpetually binding original appropriation as
advocated by some anarcho-capitalists as anathema to traditional
schools of anarchism as well as to any moral or economic philosophy
that takes equal natural rights to land and the Earth's resources as a
premise),[195] other anarcho-capitalists are closer to mutualism and
are considered part of free-market anarchism which argue that a true
free-market or laissez-faire system would be best served under
socialism rather than capitalism.[196][197]
As a whole, anarchism is seen part of the socialist tradition, with
the main divide being between anti-market anarchists (most social
anarchists, including anarcho-communists, anarcho-syndicalists and
collectivist anarchists) who support some form of decentralised
economic planning and pro-market anarchists (certain individualist
anarchists, including free-market anarchists and mutualists) who
support free-market socialism. As such, Chartier has argued that
anarcho-capitalists should reject capitalism and call themselves
free-market advocates,[198] writing that "it makes sense for
[freed-market advocates] to name what they oppose "capitalism." Doing
so calls attention to the freedom movement's radical roots, emphasizes
the value of understanding society as an alternative to the state,
underscores the fact that proponents of freedom object to
non-aggressive as well as aggressive restraints on liberty, ensures
that advocates of freedom aren't confused with people who use market
rhetoric to prop up an unjust status quo, and expresses solidarity
between defenders of freed markets and workers — as well as ordinary
people around the world who use "capitalism" as a short-hand label for
the world-system that constrains their freedom and stunts their
lives".[175]
Another major issue and divide within anarchism and anarcho-capitalism
is that of property, more specifically the issues of private property.
By property, or private property, ever since Proudhon's book What is
Property?, published in 1840, anarchists meant possession (or what
other socialists, including Marxists and communists, distingue as
personal property) which he considered as liberty ("Property is
liberty") versus productive property (such as land and infrastructure,
or what Marxists terms the means of production and the means of labor)
which he considered as theft ("Property is theft"), causing him to
also say "Property is impossible".[199]
Individualist anarchists like Tucker started calling possession as
property, or private property. Anarcho-capitalists generally make no
such distinction. Such distinction is extremely important to
anarchists and other socialists because in the capitalist mode of
production private and personal property are considered to be exactly
equivalent. They make the following distinctions:
Personal property, or possession, includes items intended for
personal use (e.g. one's toothbrush, clothes, homes, vehicles and
sometimes money).[200] It must be gained in a socially fair manner and
the owner has a distributive right to exclude others.
Anarchists generally agree that private property is a social
relationship between the owner and persons deprived (not a
relationship between person and thing), e.g. artifacts, factories,
mines, dams, infrastructure, natural vegetation, mountains, deserts
and seas. In this context, private property and ownership means
ownership of the means of production, not personal possessions.
To anarchists and socialists alike, the term private property
refers to capital or the means of production while personal property
refers to consumer and non-capital goods and services.[201][202]
Globalization
Many anarchists are actively involved in the anti-globalization
movement, seeing corporate globalization as a neocolonialist attempt
to use economic coercion on a global scale, carried out through state
institutions such as the World Bank, World Trade Organization, Group
of Eight and the World Economic Forum. Globalization is an ambiguous
term that has different meanings to different anarchist factions. Many
anarchists use the term to mean neocolonialism and/or cultural
imperialism (which they may see as related). Others, particularly
anarcho-capitalists, use globalization to mean the worldwide expansion
of the division of labor and trade which they see as beneficial so
long as governments do not intervene. Anarcho-capitalists and market
anarchists also see the worldwide expansion of the division of labor
through trade (globalization) as a boon, but they oppose the
regulation and cartelization imposed by the World Bank, World Trade
Organization and "managed trade" agreements such as the North American
Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA) and the Central America Free Trade
Agreement (CAFTA). Many also object to fiat money issued by central
banks and resulting debasement of money and confiscation of wealth.
Groups such as Reclaim the Streets[203] were among the instigators of
the so-called anti-globalization movement.[204]
The Carnival Against Capitalism on 18 June 1999 is generally regarded
as the first of the major anti-globalization protests.[205] Anarchists
such as the WOMBLES have on occasion played a significant role in
planning, organising and participating in subsequent protests.[206]
The protests tended to be organised on anarchist direct action
principles with a general tolerance for a range of different
activities ranging from those who engage in tactical frivolity to the
black blocs.[207]
Left and right anarchism
The term left anarchism, or left-wing anarchism, has been occasionally
used to distinguish social anarchism from anarcho-capitalism and
anti-state right-libertarian philosophies.[208][209] "Left anarchists"
refer to political philosophies which posit a future society in which
private property is replaced by reciprocity and non-hierarchical
society.[210][211] The term left anarchism is sometimes used
synonymously with libertarian socialism,[212] left-libertarianism, or
social anarchism.[51] Anarchists typically discourage the concept of
left-wing theories of anarchism on grounds of redundancy and that it
lends legitimacy to the notion that anarchism is compatible with
capitalism[213][214] or nationalism.[215][216]
Syndicalist Ulrike Heider categorized anarchism into left anarchism,
right anarchism and green anarchism.[217] The term right anarchism, or
right-wing anarchism, has been used to refer to schools of thoughts
which are not generally considered part of anarchism, including
anarcho-capitalism[66][68] and national-anarchism.[218]
Nationalism
Main article: Anarchism and nationalism
See also: National-anarchism and Postcolonial anarchism
Anarchism has a long history of opposing imperialism, both in the core
nations (the colonizers) and the periphery nations (the colonized). In
general, anarchists have preferred to focus on building revolutions at
home and doing solidarity work for comrades in other countries, e.g.
Guy Aldred was jailed for printing Shyamji Krishnavarma's The Indian
Sociologist. Another example of this was Rudolf Rocker, a prominent
German anarchist and anti-fascist who was particularly active amongst
Jewish workers. In his Nationalism and Culture, he argued for a
"federation of European peoples" which would include Jews. Rejecting
biological theories of race and the concept of nation, he argued that
since it was European states that had conquered and colonized the rest
of the world, successful libertarian organization amongst Europeans
was "the first condition for the creation of a world federation which
will also secure the so-called colonial peoples the same rights for
the pursuit of happiness. Many modern anarchists and other
anti-imperialists share this approach.[219]
Historically, anarchism was supportive of the anationalist movement as
well as of the Esperanto language,[220][221] a language constructed to
serve as a politically and ethnically neutral international language.
After the Spanish Civil War, Francoist Spain persecuted anarchists and
Catalan nationalists, among whom the use of Esperanto was
extensive.[222] The so-called national-anarchist movement is not
recognized as part of anarchism by anarchists and scholars due to
anarchism opposition to nationalism, the nation state, tribalism and
neo-tribalism and national-anarchism's perceived racism and sexism,
arguing that it represents a further evolution in the thinking of the
radical right rather than an entirely new
dimension.[223][224][225][226] Some accuse national-anarchists of
being white nationalists who promote ethnic and racial separatism
while others argue they want the militant chic of calling themselves
anarchists without the historical and philosophical baggage that
accompanies such a claim.[227][228]
During the 2014 Scottish independence referendum, there was debate
within anarchist circles about whether to take an abstentionist
position, vote for independence,[90] or to vote to remain in the
United Kingdom,[91] therefore anarchists rarely fitted into the easy
binary of Yes/No voters of the referendum,[229] with all seeking to go
beyond the choices offered at the ballot box. There was also a debate
about what Scottish independence would mean for the anarchist movement
and social struggle.[92] Groups like the Anarchist Federation in
Scotland (mainly in Edinburgh and Glasgow) took a critical stance
skeptical of the benefits of Scottish independence.[91][93] Scottish
anarchists argued that Scottish independence and Scottish nationalism
diverted energy away from grassroots struggles and that the movement
for Scottish independence sucked people towards Scottish nationalism
and electoral politics.[230]
Environment
See also: Anarcho-primitivism, Ecofeminism, Green anarchism, Green
syndicalism, and Social ecology
The environment and sustainability have been an issue for anarchists
from at least as far back as Peter Kropotkin's 1899 book Fields,
Factories and Workshops, but since the late 1970s anarchists in
English-speaking world and European countries have been agitating for
the natural environment. Eco-anarchists or green anarchists often
embrace deep ecology, a worldview that strives to cultivate
biodiversity and sustainability. Eco-anarchists often use direct
action against what they see as Earth-destroying institutions. Of
particular importance is the Earth First! movement that takes action
such as tree sitting. The more militant Earth Liberation Front which
grew out of Earth First! also has connections with the anarchist
movement. Another important component is ecofeminism which sees the
domination of nature as a metaphor for the domination of women.
Murray Bookchin's work on social ecology, David Watson's work with
Fifth Estate magazine, Steve Booth's work in the United Kingdom
publication Green Anarchist and Graham Purchase's writings on green
syndicalism have all contributed to the broad variety and scope of
green anarchist/eco-anarchist thought and action. Green anarchism also
involves a critique of industrial capitalism and for some green
anarchists (including anarcho-primitivists) civilization itself.
Relations with the left
On May 1937 the President of Republican Spain, Manuel Azaña, then
living in the parliament house in Exposition Park, talked by telephone
to the President of Catalonia, Luis Companys, who was in his office in
the Palace of the Generalitat. The conversation had been going on for
some time, when it was sharply interrupted by an anarchist in the
Telefónica who said: "This conversation will have to stop. We have
more interesting things to do than listen to your stupid
conversations." The line was then broken.
—Jaume Miravitlles[231]
While many anarchists (especially those involved in the
anti-globalization movement) continue to see themselves as a leftist
movement, some thinkers and activists believe it is necessary to
re-evaluate anarchism's relationship with the traditional left. Like
many radical ideologies, most anarchist schools of thought are to some
degree sectarian. There is often a difference of opinion within each
school about how to react to, or interact with, other schools. Many
anarchists draw from a wide range of political perspectives, such as
the Zapatista Army of National Liberation, the Situationists,
ultra-leftists, autonomist Marxism and various indigenous cultures.
A movement called post-left anarchy seeks to distance itself from the
traditional left—communists, socialists, social democrats and the
like—and to escape the confines of ideology in general. Post-leftists
argue that anarchism has been weakened by its long attachment to
contrary leftist movements and single issue causes (anti-war,
anti-nuclear and so on). It calls for a synthesis of anarchist thought
and a specifically anti-authoritarian revolutionary movement outside
of the leftist milieu. Important groups and individuals associated
with post-left anarchy include CrimethInc., the magazine Anarchy: A
Journal of Desire Armed and its editor Jason McQuinn, Bob Black, Hakim
Bey and others.
The term post-anarchism was originated by Saul Newman, first receiving
popular attention in his book From Bakunin to Lacan, a synthesis of
classical anarchist theory and poststructuralist thought. Subsequent
to Newman's use of the term, it has taken on a life of its own and a
wide range of ideas including autonomism, post-left anarchy,
Situationism, postcolonialism and Zapatismo. By its very nature,
post-anarchism rejects the idea that it should be a coherent set of
doctrines and beliefs. Key thinkers nonetheless associated with
post-anarchism include Saul Newman, Todd May, Gilles Deleuze and Félix
Guattari.[232]
Some activists calling themselves insurrectionary anarchists are
critical of formal anarchist labor unions and federations and advocate
informal organization, carrying out acts of resistance in various
struggles. Proponents include Wolfi Landstreicher and Alfredo M.
Bonanno, author of works including Armed Joy and The Anarchist
Tension. This tendency is represented in the United States in
magazines such as Willful Disobedience and Killing King Abacus.
Communism
While communism is proposed as a form of social and economic
organisation by many anarchists, other anarchists consider it a danger
to the liberty and free development of the individual.[233] Most
schools of anarchism have recognized a distinction between libertarian
and authoritarian forms of communism.[234] Pierre-Joseph Proudhon said
of communism that "whether of the utopian or the Marxist variety, that
it destroyed freedom by taking away from the individual control over
his means of production",[235] adding: "Communism is exploitation of
the strong by the weak".[236] Mikhail Bakunin stated: "I hate
Communism because it is the negation of liberty and because for me
humanity is unthinkable without liberty. I am not a Communist, because
Communism concentrates and swallows up in itself for the benefit of
the State all the forces of society, because it inevitably leads to
the concentration of property in the hands of the State".[237]
However, Bakunin was speaking of authoritarian and statist forms of
communism and socialism (see also state capitalism and its origins and
early uses of the term) as verified by the last line which mentions
state property—anarcho-communists explicitly reject state property and
authority, especially centralized authority—and famously proclaimed:
"We are convinced that freedom without Socialism is privilege and
injustice, and that Socialism without freedom is slavery and
brutality".[238] Even American individualist anarchist Benjamin
Tucker, who insisted on the voluntary nature of all association and
opposed communism along with majority rule, organized religion and the
institution of marriage due to their compulsory nature,[239] argued:
"Whoever denies private property is of necessity an Archist. This
excludes from Anarchism all believers in compulsory Communism. As for
the believers in voluntary Communism (of whom there are precious few),
they are of necessity believers in the liberty to hold private
property, for to pool one's possessions with those of others is
nothing more or less than an exercise of proprietorship".[111]
Karl Marx's communist society is actually based on free association
which he called a community of freely associated individuals.[240]
Marx's communist society is one in which "the full and free
development of every individual forms the ruling principle" and "the
free development of each is the condition for the free development of
all".[241] Hence, Marx justified the forms of equality he did advocate
such as the communal ownership and control of the economy on the
grounds that they led to human freedom and human development, arguing
that "the realm of freedom actually begins only where labor which is
determined by necessity and mundane considerations ceases; thus in the
very nature of things it lies beyond the sphere of actual material
production.[242] According to Allen Woods, a communist society is one
that has transcended class antagonisms and "would not be one in which
some truly universal interest at last reigns, to which individual
interests must be sacrificed. It would instead be a society in which
individuals freely act as the truly human individuals they are",
making Marx's communist society radically individualistic.[126]
Although Peter Kropotkin, one of the leading proponents of
anarcho-communism while also opposing statist communism, argued for an
economic model of free distribution between all individuals, many
individualist anarchists oppose communism in all its forms on the
grounds that voluntary communism is not practicable. Individualist
anarchists such as Benjamin Tucker, Victor Yarros and Henry Appleton
have denied that communism is a genuine form of anarchism.[243] They
rejected its strategies and argued that it is inherently
authoritarian.[244] In the opinion of Appleton, "Communism, being
opposed to natural law, must necessarily call upon unnatural methods
if it would put itself into practice" and employ "pillage, brute
force, and violence".[245] As a response, Albert Meltzer argued that
since individualist anarchists like Tucker promote the idea of private
armies, they actually support a "limited State", contending that it
"is only possible to conceive of Anarchism which is free, communistic
and offering no economic necessity for repression of countering
it".[112] Anarcho-communists also reject the criticism, pointing to
the principle of voluntary association that underpins their theory and
differentiates it from statist communism.[113] Some individualist
anarchists are willing to recognize such communism as a legitimate
form. Kevin Carson writes that "free market, libertarian communist,
syndicalism, and other kinds of collectivist anarchists must learn to
coexist in peace and mutual respect today, in our fight against the
corporate state, and tomorrow, in the panarchy that is likely to
succeed it".[114]
As a response, there emerged in the 1980s United States the tendency
of post-left anarchy which was influenced profoundly by egoism in
aspects such as the critique of ideology. Jason McQuinn says that
"when I (and other anti-ideological anarchists) criticize ideology, it
is always from a specifically critical, anarchist perspective rooted
in both the skeptical, individualist-anarchist philosophy of Max
Stirner".[246] Bob Black and Feral Faun/Wolfi Landstreicher also
strongly adhere to Stirnerist egoism. A reprinting of The Right to be
Greedy in the 1980s was done with the involvement of Black who also
wrote the preface to it.[120] In the book's preface, Black has
humorously suggested the idea of "Marxist Stirnerism" just as he wrote
an essay on "groucho-marxism",[122] writing: "If Marxism-Stirnerism is
conceivable, every orthodoxy prating of freedom or liberation is
called into question, anarchism included. The only reason to read this
book, as its authors would be the first to agree, is for what you can
get out of it".[120]
Hakim Bey has said: "From Stirner's "Union of Self-Owning Ones" we
proceed to Nietzsche's circle of "Free Spirits" and thence to Charles
Fourier's "Passional Series", doubling and redoubling ourselves even
as the Other multiplies itself in the eros of the group".[247] Bey
also wrote: "The Mackay Society, of which Mark & I are active members,
is devoted to the anarchism of Max Stirner, Benj. Tucker & John Henry
Mackay. [...] The Mackay Society, incidentally, represents a
little-known current of individualist thought which never cut its ties
with revolutionary labor. Dyer Lum, Ezra & Angela Haywood represent
this school of thought; Jo Labadie, who wrote for Tucker's Liberty,
made himself a link between the American "plumb-line" anarchists, the
"philosophical" individualists, & the syndicalist or communist branch
of the movement; his influence reached the Mackay Society through his
son, Laurance. Like the Italian Stirnerites (who influenced us through
our late friend Enrico Arrigoni) we support all anti-authoritarian
currents, despite their apparent contradictions".[248]
Marxism
Anarchism has had a strained relationship with Marxism since Karl
Marx's life. The dispute between Marx and Mikhail Bakunin highlighted
the differences between anarchism and Marxism, with Bakunin
criticizing Marx for his authoritarian bent.[249] Bakunin also
argued—against certain ideas of a number of Marxists—that not all
revolutions need to be violent. For instance, he strongly rejected
Marx's concept of the dictatorship of the proletariat, a concept that
vanguardist socialism, including Marxist–Leninism, would use to
justify one-party rule from above by a party representing the
proletariat.[250] Bakunin insisted that revolutions must be led by the
people directly while any "enlightened elite" must only exert
influence by remaining "invisible [...] not imposed on anyone [...]
[and] deprived of all official rights and significance".[251] He held
that the state should be immediately abolished because all forms of
government eventually lead to oppression.[250]
Bakunin has sometimes been called the first theorist of the concept of
a new class, meaning that a class of intellectuals and bureaucrats
running the state in the name of the people or the proletariat—but in
reality in their own interests alone. Bakunin argued that the "State
has always been the patrimony of some privileged class: a priestly
class, an aristocratic class, a bourgeois class. And finally, when all
the other classes have exhausted themselves, the State then becomes
the patrimony of the bureaucratic class and then falls—or, if you
will, rises—to the position of a machine". Bakunin also had a
different view as compared to Marx's on the revolutionary potential of
the lumpenproletariat and the proletariat. As such, "[b]oth agreed
that the proletariat would play a key role, but for Marx the
proletariat was the exclusive, leading revolutionary agent while
Bakunin entertained the possibility that the peasants and even the
lumpenproletariat (the unemployed, common criminals, etc.) could rise
to the occasion".[252] Bakunin "considers workers' integration in
capital as destructive of more primary revolutionary forces. For
Bakunin, the revolutionary archetype is found in a peasant milieu
(which is presented as having longstanding insurrectionary traditions,
as well as a communist archetype in its current social form—the
peasant commune) and amongst educated unemployed youth, assorted
marginals from all classes, brigands, robbers, the impoverished
masses, and those on the margins of society who have escaped, been
excluded from, or not yet subsumed in the discipline of emerging
industrial work. [...] [I]n short, all those whom Marx sought to
include in the category of the lumpenproletariat".[253]
While both anarchists and Marxists share the same final goal, the
creation of a free, egalitarian society without social classes and
government, they strongly disagree on how to achieve this goal.
Anarchists, especially social anarchists, believe that the classless,
stateless society should be established by the direct action of the
masses, culminating in social revolution and refusing any intermediate
stage such as the dictatorship of the proletariat on the basis that
such a dictatorship will become a self-perpetuating fundament.
However, libertarian Marxists argue that Marx used the phrase to mean
that the worker control at the point of production and not a party
would still be a state until society is reorganized according to
socialist principles. For Bakunin, the fundamental contradiction is
that for the Marxists "anarchism or freedom is the aim, while the
state and dictatorship is the means, and so, in order to free the
masses, they have first to be enslaved".[254] Ultimately, the main
divide between anarchism and Marxism is between decentralisation and
centralisation, with anarchists favouring decentralisation and
Marxists arguing that due to the Industrial Revolution and later
stages of the Industrial Revolution a certain degree of authority and
centralisation has become necessary or inevitable.[255]
Anarchists and many non-Marxist libertarian socialists reject the need
for a transitory state phase, claiming that socialism can only be
established through decentralized, non-coercive organization. The
phrases barracks socialism or barracks communism became a shorthand
for this critique, evoking the image of citizens' lives being as
regimented as the lives of conscripts in a barracks.[256] Ironically,
the term barracks communism[257] (Kasernenkommunismus)[258] was coined
by Marx himself[259] to refer to a crude, authoritarian, forced
collectivism and communism where all aspects of life are
bureaucratically regimented and communal. Originally, Marx used the
expression to criticise the vision of Sergey Nechayev outlined in "The
Fundamentals of the Future Social System"[259][260] which had a major
influence on other Russian revolutionaries like Pyotr Tkachev and
Vladimir Lenin.[261][262][263][264][265][266][excessive citations] The
term barracks here does not refer to military barracks, but to the
workers' barracks-type primitive dormitories in which industrial
workers lived in many places in the Russian Empire of the time.[267]
Later, political theorists of the Soviet Union applied this term to
China under Mao Zedong.[257] Still later during the Soviet perestroika
period, the term was used to apply to the history of the Soviet Union
itself.[267]
Noam Chomsky is critical of Marxism's dogmatic strains and the idea of
Marxism itself, but he still appreciates Marx's contributions to
political thought. Unlike some anarchists, Chomsky does not consider
Bolshevism "Marxism in practice", but he does recognize that Marx was
a complicated figure who had conflicting ideas. While acknowledging
the latent authoritarianism in Marx, Chomsky also points to the
libertarian strains that developed into the council communism of Rosa
Luxemburg and Anton Pannekoek. However, his commitment to libertarian
socialism has led him to characterize himself as an anarchist with
radical Marxist leanings. As a response to those critiques,
libertarian Marxism refers to a broad scope of economic and political
philosophies that emphasize the anti-authoritarian aspects of Marxism.
Early currents of libertarian Marxism, known as left communism,
emerged in opposition to Marxism–Leninism[268] and its derivatives
such as Stalinism and Maoism, among others. Libertarian Marxism is
also often critical of reformist positions, such as those held by
social democrats. Libertarian Marxist currents often draw from Marx
and Friedrich Engels' later works, specifically the Grundrisse and The
Civil War in France,[269] emphasizing the Marxist belief in the
ability of the working class to forge its own destiny without the need
for a revolutionary party or state to mediate or aid its
liberation.[270] Along with anarchism, libertarian Marxism is one of
the main currents of libertarian socialism.[271]
See also
Anarchism and issues related to love and sex
Explanatory notes
In reality, Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels rejected equality as a
social ideal and as a permanent yardstick against which social
arrangements should be judged. This can be seen in their reaction to
the programme of the Social Democratic Workers' Party of Germany
(SDAP).[123]
In March 1875, Engels complained in a letter to August Bebel (one
of the founders and leaders of the SDAP which in 1875 merged with the
General German Workers' Association into the Socialist Workers' Party
of Germany) that the programme mistakenly advocated "[t]he elimination
of all social and political inequality" rather than "the abolition of
all class distinctions". For Engels, the goal of total social equality
was impossible and represented the ambitions of an underdeveloped form
of socialism, arguing and making the following point as an example:
As between one country, one province and even one place and
another, living conditions will always evince a certain inequality
which may be reduced to a minimum but never wholly eliminated. The
living conditions of Alpine dwellers will always be different from
those of the plainsmen. The concept of a socialist society as a realm
of equality is a one-sided French concept deriving from the old
"liberty, equality, fraternity," a concept which was justified in
that, in its own time and place, it signified a phase of development,
but which, like all the one-sided ideas of earlier socialist schools,
ought now to be superseded, since they produce nothing but mental
confusion, and more accurate ways of presenting the matter have been
discovered.[124]
In Philosophy and Real Politics (2008), Raymond Geuss argues that
Marx makes two main points about equality in his 1875 Critique of the
Gotha Programme. Firstly, Marx claims that it makes no sense to speak
of equality in the abstract because we can only understand what it
means for x to be equal or unequal with y if we first specify the
dimensions along which they are being compared. For x to be equal to y
is for them to be equal in a particular concrete respect. If x and y
are people then they can only be judged equal relative to particular
criteria such as their height, how many shoes they own, or how much
cake they have eaten. Therefore, one can only be in favour of equality
along specific dimensions such as equality of cake consumption and
never equality as an abstract ideal. Secondly, Marx claims that
advocating equality along one dimension such as everyone in a society
earning the same amount of money per hour worked will lead to
inequality along other dimensions. If everyone earning an equal amount
per hour of work would lead to those who work more having more money
than those who work less. As a result, those unable to work a large
amount, if at all, such as disabled people, old people, or women who
are expected to do the majority of housework, will be unequal with
those who can work more such as the able-bodied, young people, or men.
Those doing manual labour and so unable to work long hours due to
fatigue will be unequal to those who engage in non-manual labour and
so can work more hours. If a society decides to instead ensure
equality of income by paying all workers the same daily wage, then
there would still be inequality along other dimensions. Workers who do
not have to provide for a family with their wage will have more
disposable income than workers with families. Therefore, Geuss argues
that we can never reach full equality, but merely move equality and
inequality around along different dimensions.[125]
In Marx on Equality (2014), Allen Woods similarly argued that
"Marx thinks the idea of equality is actually a vehicle for bourgeois
class oppression, and something quite different from the communist
goal of the abolition of classes. [...] A society that has transcended
class antagonisms, therefore, would not be one in which some truly
universal interest at last reigns, to which individual interests must
be sacrificed. It would instead be a society in which individuals
freely act as the truly human individuals they are. Marx's radical
communism was, in this way, also radically individualistic".[126]
References
Malatesta, Errico. "Towards Anarchism". Man!. Los Angeles:
International Group of San Francisco. OCLC 3930443. Agrell, Siri (14
May 2007). "Working for The Man". The Globe and Mail. Archived from
the original on 16 May 2007. Retrieved 14 April 2008. "Anarchism".
Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica Premium Service.
2006. Archived from the original on 14 December 2006. Retrieved 29
August 2006. "Anarchism". The Shorter Routledge Encyclopedia of
Philosophy: 14. 2005. "Anarchism is the view that a society without
the state, or government, is both possible and desirable". The
following sources cite anarchism as a political philosophy:
Mclaughlin, Paul (2007). Anarchism and Authority. Aldershot: Ashgate.
p. 59. ISBN 978-0-7546-6196-2. Johnston, R. (2000). The Dictionary of
Human Geography. Cambridge: Blackwell Publishers. p. 24. ISBN
0-631-20561-6.
Slevin, Carl (2003). McLean, Aiaun; McMillan, Allistair, eds.
"Anarchism". The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Politics. Oxford
University Press.
"Principles of The International of Anarchist Federations".
Archived 5 January 2012 at the Wayback Machine International of
Anarchist Federations. "The IAF – IFA fights for : the abolition of
all forms of authority whether economical, political, social,
religious, cultural or sexual".
Goldman, Emma. "What it Really Stands for Anarchy". Anarchism and
Other Essays. "Anarchism, then, really stands for the liberation of
the human mind from the dominion of religion; the liberation of the
human body from the dominion of property; liberation from the shackles
and restraint of government. Anarchism stands for a social order based
on the free grouping of individuals for the purpose of producing real
social wealth; an order that will guarantee to every human being free
access to the earth and full enjoyment of the necessities of life,
according to individual desires, tastes, and inclinations".
Tucker, Benjamin. Individual Liberty. "They found that they must
turn either to the right or to the left, — follow either the path of
Authority or the path of Liberty. Marx went one way; Warren and
Proudhon the other. Thus were born State Socialism and Anarchism.
[...] Authority, takes many shapes, but, broadly speaking, her enemies
divide themselves into three classes: first, those who abhor her both
as a means and as an end of progress, opposing her openly, avowedly,
sincerely, consistently, universally; second, those who profess to
believe in her as a means of progress, but who accept her only so far
as they think she will subserve their own selfish interests, denying
her and her blessings to the rest of the world; third, those who
distrust her as a means of progress, believing in her only as an end
to be obtained by first trampling upon, violating, and outraging her.
These three phases of opposition to Liberty are met in almost every
sphere of thought and human activity. Good representatives of the
first are seen in the Catholic Church and the Russian autocracy; of
the second, in the Protestant Church and the Manchester school of
politics and political economy; of the third, in the atheism of
Gambetta and the socialism of the socialism off Karl Marx".
Ward, Colin (1966). "Anarchism as a Theory of Organization".
Archived from the original on 25 March 2010. Retrieved 1 March 2010.
Anarchist historian George Woodcock report of Mikhail Bakunin's
anti-authoritarianism and shows opposition to both state and non-state
forms of authority as follows: "All anarchists deny authority; many of
them fight against it". (p. 9) "[...] Bakunin did not convert the
League's central committee to his full program, but he did persuade
them to accept a remarkably radical recommendation to the Berne
Congress of September 1868, demanding economic equality and implicitly
attacking authority in both Church and State".
Brown, L. Susan (2002). "Anarchism as a Political Philosophy of
Existential Individualism: Implications for Feminism". The Politics of
Individualism: Liberalism, Liberal Feminism and Anarchism. Black Rose
Books Ltd. Publishing. p. 106.
Kropotkin, Peter. "Anarchism: its philosophy and ideal". "That is
why Anarchy, when it works to destroy authority in all its aspects,
when it demands the abrogation of laws and the abolition of the
mechanism that serves to impose them, when it refuses all hierarchical
organization and preaches free agreement — at the same time strives to
maintain and enlarge the precious kernel of social customs without
which no human or animal society can exist".
"B.1 Why are anarchists against authority and hierarchy?". An
Anarchist FAQ. "Anarchists are opposed to irrational (e.g.,
illegitimate) authority, in other words, hierarchy — hierarchy being
the institutionalisation of authority within a society".
Woodcock, George. "Anarchism". Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
"ANARCHISM, a social philosophy that rejects authoritarian government
and maintains that voluntary institutions are best suited to express
man's natural social tendencies".
Kropotkin, Peter. "Anarchism". Encyclopædia Britannica. "In a
society developed on these lines, the voluntary associations which
already now begin to cover all the fields of human activity would take
a still greater extension so as to substitute themselves for the state
in all its functions".
McLean; McMillan 2003; Craig 2005, p. 14.
McLaughlin 2007, p. 28. "Anarchists do reject the state, as we
will see. But to claim that this central aspect of anarchism is
definitive is to sell anarchism short".
Proudhon 1849. "Anarchy is the condition of existence of adult
society, as hierarchy is the condition of primitive society. There is
a continual progress in human society from hierarchy to anarchy".
Bakunin 1882. "In a word, we reject all legislation, all
authority, and all privileged, licensed, official, and legal
influence, even though arising from universal suffrage, convinced that
it can turn only to the advantage of a dominant minority of exploiters
against the interests of the immense majority in subjection to them.
This is the sense in which we are really Anarchists".
Armand 1926. "In practice, any individual who, because of his or
her temperament or because of conscious and serious reflection,
repudiates all external authority or coercion, whether of a
governmental, ethical, intellectual, or economic order, can be
considered an anarchist. Everyone who consciously rejects the
domination of people by other people or by the social ambiance, and
its economic corollaries, can be said to be an anarchist as well".
Wilbur, Shawn P. (19 February 2018). "The Anarchist Encyclopedia:
Hierarchy". Libertarian Labyrinth. "The anarchists are against all
hierarchy, be it moral or material. They oppose to it the respect for
liberty and the absolute autonomy of the individual".
Brooks 1994, p. xi; Kahn 2000; Moynihan 2007.
Guerin 1970, p. 35.
Marshall 1993, pp. 14–17.
Sylvan 2007, p. 262.
McLean; McMillan 2003.
Fowler 1972; Kropotkin 2002, p. 5; Ostergaard 2009, p. 14.
Rines, George Edwin, ed. (1918). "Anarchism". The Encyclopedia
Americana: A Library of Universal Knowledge. Vol. 1. New York. p. 624.
LCCN 18016023. OCLC 7308909 – via Hathi Trust.
Hamilton, Peter (1995). Émile Durkheim. New York: Routledge. p.
79. ISBN 978-0415110471.
Faguet, Émile (1970). Politicians & Moralists of the Nineteenth
Century. Freeport: Books for Libraries Press. p. 147. ISBN
978-0-8369-1828-1.
Bowen, James; Purkis, Jon (2004). Changing Anarchism: Anarchist
Theory and Practice in a Global Age. Manchester University Press. p.
24. ISBN 9780719066948.
Knowles, Rob (Winter 2000). "Political Economy From Below:
Communitarian Anarchism as a Neglected Discourse in Histories of
Economic Thought". History of Economics Review. 31 (31): 30–47.
doi:10.1080/10370196.2000.11733332. S2CID 141027974.
Honderich, Ted (1995). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford
University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-866132-0.
Carter, April (1978). "Anarchism and violence". Nomos. American
Society for Political and Legal Philosophy. 19: 320–340. JSTOR
24219053.
Trevijano, Carmen García (2001). Ted Honderich (ed.). Enciclopedia
Oxford de filosofía (in Spanish). Tecnos. ISBN 978-84-309-3699-1.
Fiala, Andrew (2017). "Anarchism". Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
Williams, Dana M. (2018). "Contemporary anarchist and anarchistic
movements". Sociology Compass. 12 (6). Wiley. doi:10.1111/soc4.12582.
ISSN 1751-9020.
Williams, Dana M. (2019). "Tactics: Conceptions of Social Change,
Revolution, and Anarchist Organisation". In Levy, Carl; Adams, Matthew
S. (eds.). The Palgrave Handbook of Anarchism. Springer Publishing.
ISBN 978-3-319-75620-2.
McLaughlin 2007, pp 25–26.
Richard Theodore Ely, Socialism: An Examination of Its Nature, Its
Strength and Its Weakness (New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1894), p. 3.
Tucker, Benjamin. State Socialism and Anarchism: How Far They
Agree and Wherein They Differ.
McLean and McMillan 2003.
Anarchism; Fowler 1972; Kropotkin 2002, p. 5; Ostergaard 2009, p. 14.
Anarchist survey highlighting a general opposition to capitalism:
"2010 Anarchist Survey report". Archived from the original on 14 March
2012. Retrieved 8 November 2010.
Chomsky, Noam (1991). "On Capitalism". Chomsky.info. Archived from
the original on 28 September 2013. Retrieved 26 November 2013.
"catastrophe of capitalism"
Anarchist FAQ collective. "Is "anarcho-capitalism" a form of
capitalism?". Archived from the original on 2 December 2013. Retrieved
26 November 2013.
Iverson, Stan. (1968). "Sex and Anarcho-socialism". Sex Marchers.
p. 57. "Libertarian Socialism, or if you please, anarcho-socialism
[...]".
Walford, George (1979). Ideologies and Their Functions: A Study in
Systematic Ideology. pp. 139–145.
McNally, David (1993). "'Proudhon did Enormous Mischief': Marx's
Critique of the First Market Socialists". Against the Market:
Political Economy, Market Socialism and the Marxist Critique. Verso.
Sturgis, Amy H. (2003). Presidents from Hayes Through McKinley:
Debating the Issues in Pro and Con Primary Documents. Greenwood
Publishing Group. p. 106. "Composed of many differing strains of
thought (such as mutualism, anarcho-individualism, anarcho-socialism,
and anarcho-communism), anarchism revolves around the concept of
noncoercion and the belief that force is illegitimate and unethical".
Busky, Donald F. (1 January 2000). Democratic Socialism: A Global
Survey. Greenwood Publishing Group. p. 2. ISBN 9780275968861. "The
same may be said of anarchism: social anarchism—a nonstate form of
socialism—may be distinguished from the nonsocialist, and, in some
cases, procapitalist school of individualist anarchism".
Ostergaard, Geoffrey (2008). "Anarchism". The Blackwell Dictionary
of Modern Social Thought. Blackwell Publishing. p. 14.
Bylund, Per (19 March 2019). "The Trouble With Socialist
Anarchism". Mises Institute. Retrieved 31 March 2019.
Thagard, Paul. 2002. Coherence in Thought and Action. MIT Press. p. 153.
Heider, Ulrike (1994). Anarchism: Left, Right and Green. San
Francisco: City Lights Books.
Baginki, Max (May 1907). "Stirner: The Ego and His Own". Mother
Earth (2: 3). "Modern Communists are more individualistic than
Stirner. To them, not merely religion, morality, family and State are
spooks, but property also is no more than a spook, in whose name the
individual is enslaved — and how enslaved! [...] Communism thus
creates a basis for the liberty and Eigenheit of the individual. I am
a Communist because I am an Individualist. Fully as heartily the
Communists concur with Stirner when he puts the word take in place of
demand — that leads to the dissolution of property, to expropriation.
Individualism and Communism go hand in hand."; Novatore, Renzo (1924).
"Towards the Creative Nothing"; Gray, Christopher (1974). Leaving the
Twentieth Century. p. 88; Black, Bob (2010). "Nightmares of Reason".
"[C]ommunism is the final fulfillment of individualism. [...] The
apparent contradiction between individualism and communism rests on a
misunderstanding of both. [...] Subjectivity is also objective: the
individual really is subjective. It is nonsense to speak of
"emphatically prioritizing the social over the individual," [...]. You
may as well speak of prioritizing the chicken over the egg. Anarchy is
a "method of individualization." It aims to combine the greatest
individual development with the greatest communal unity".
Kropotkin, Peter (1901). "Communism and Anarchy". "Communism is
the one which guarantees the greatest amount of individual liberty —
provided that the idea that begets the community be Liberty, Anarchy
[...]. Communism guarantees economic freedom better than any other
form of association, because it can guarantee wellbeing, even luxury,
in return for a few hours of work instead of a day's work."; Truda,
Dielo (1926). "Organisational Platform of the Libertarian Communists".
"This other society will be libertarian communism, in which social
solidarity and free individuality find their full expression, and in
which these two ideas develop in perfect harmony."; "My Perspectives".
Willful Disobedience (2: 12). "I see the dichotomies made between
individualism and communism, individual revolt and class struggle, the
struggle against human exploitation and the exploitation of nature as
false dichotomies and feel that those who accept them are
impoverishing their own critique and struggle."; Brown, L. Susan
(2002). The Politics of Individualism. Black Rose Books; Brown, L.
Susan (2 February 2011). "Does Work Really Work?".
Morriss, Brian (1993). Bakukunin: The Philosophy of Freedom. Black
Rose Books Ltd. p. 115.
Bookchin, Murray (1995). "Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism:
An Unbridgeable Chasm". The Anarchist Library. Retrieved 31 March
2019.
Ehrlich, Howard J. (2013). "The Best of Social Anarchism" Archived
2019-03-31 at the Wayback Machine. See Sharp Press. Retrieved 31 March
2019.
Esenwein, George Richard (1989). Anarchist Ideology and the
Working Class Movement in Spain, 1868-1898. p. 135. "Anarchism without
adjectives referred to an unhyphenated form of anarchism, that is, a
doctrine without any qualifying labels such as communist,
collectivist, mutualist, or individualist. For others, [...] [it] was
simply understood as an attitude that tolerated the coexistence of
different anarchist schools".
Bowen, James; Purkis, Jon (2004). Changing Anarchism: Anarchist
Theory and Practice in a Global Age. Manchester University Press. p.
24. ISBN 9780719066948.
Knowles, Rob (Winter 2000). "Political Economy From Below:
Communitarian Anarchism as a Neglected Discourse in Histories of
Economic Thought". History of Economics Review. 31 (31): 30–47.
doi:10.1080/10370196.2000.11733332. S2CID 141027974.
Hamilton, Peter (1995). Émile Durkheim. New York: Routledge. p.
79. ISBN 978-0415110471.
Faguet, Émile (1970). Politicians & Moralists of the Nineteenth
Century. Freeport: Books for Libraries Press. p. 147. ISBN
978-0-8369-1828-1.
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph (1848). What Is Property?.
"G.1.4 Why is the social context important in evaluating
Individualist Anarchism?". An Anarchist FAQ. Archived 15 March 2013 at
the Wayback Machine
Brooks, Frank H. (1994). The Individualist Anarchists: An
Anthology of Liberty (1881–1908). Transaction Publishers. p. 75.
Marshall, Peter (1993). Demanding the Impossible: A History of
Anarchism. Oakland, California: PM Press. p. 565. ISBN
978-1-60486-064-1.: "In fact, few anarchists would accept the
'anarcho-capitalists' into the anarchist camp since they do not share
a concern for economic equality and social justice, Their
self-interested, calculating market men would be incapable of
practising voluntary co-operation and mutual aid. Anarcho-capitalists,
even if they do reject the State, might therefore best be called
right-wing libertarians rather than anarchists."; Sabatini, Peter
(Fall/Winter 1994–1995). "Libertarianism: Bogus Anarchy". Anarchy: A
Journal of Desire Armed (41). "Within Libertarianism, Rothbard
represents a minority perspective that actually argues for the total
elimination of the state. However Rothbard's claim as an anarchist is
quickly voided when it is shown that he only wants an end to the
public state. In its place he allows countless private states, with
each person supplying their own police force, army, and law, or else
purchasing these services from capitalist venders. [...] [S]o what
remains is shrill anti-statism conjoined to a vacuous freedom in
hackneyed defense of capitalism. In sum, the "anarchy" of
Libertarianism reduces to a liberal fraud."; Meltzer, Albert (1
January 2000). Anarchism: Arguments for and Against. AK Press. p. 50.
ISBN 978-1-873176-57-3. "The philosophy of "anarcho-capitalism"
dreamed up by the "libertarian" New Right, has nothing to do with
Anarchism as known by the Anarchist movement proper."; Goodway, David
(2006). Anarchist Seeds Beneath the Snow. Liverpool Press. p. 4. ISBN
978-1-84631-025-6.: "'Libertarian' and 'libertarianism' are frequently
employed by anarchists as synonyms for 'anarchist' and 'anarchism',
largely as an attempt to distance themselves from the negative
connotations of 'anarchy' and its derivatives. The situation has been
vastly complicated in recent decades with the rise of
anarcho-capitalism, 'minimal statism' and an extreme right-wing
laissez-faire philosophy advocated by such theorists as Murray
Rothbard and Robert Nozick and their adoption of the words
'libertarian' and 'libertarianism'. It has therefore now become
necessary to distinguish between their right libertarianism and the
left libertarianism of the anarchist tradition."; Newman, Saul (2010).
The Politics of Postanarchism. Edinburgh University Press. p. 53. ISBN
978-0-7486-3495-8.: "It is important to distinguish between anarchism
and certain strands of right-wing libertarianism which at times go by
the same name (for example, Murray Rothbard's anarcho-capitalism).
There is a complex debate within this tradition between those like
Robert Nozick, who advocate a 'minimal state', and those like Rothbard
who want to do away with the state altogether and allow all
transactions to be governed by the market alone. From an anarchist
perspective, however, both positions—the minimal state (minarchist)
and the no-state ('anarchist') positions—neglect the problem of
economic domination; in other words, they neglect the hierarchies,
oppressions, and forms of exploitation that would inevitably arise in
a laissez-faire 'free' market. [...] Anarchism, therefore, has no
truck with this right-wing libertarianism, not only because it
neglects economic inequality and domination, but also because in
practice (and theory) it is highly inconsistent and contradictory. The
individual freedom invoked by right-wing libertarians is only a narrow
economic freedom within the constraints of a capitalist market, which,
as anarchists show, is no freedom at all".
See also the following sources:
K, David (2005). What is Anarchism?. Bastard Press.
Marshall, Peter (1992). Demanding the Impossible. Chapther 38.
London: Fontana Press. ISBN 0-00-686245-4.
MacSaorsa, Iain (2009). Is 'Anarcho' Capitalism Against the
State?. Spunk Press.
Wells, Sam (January 1979). Anarcho-Capitalism is Not
Anarchism, and Political Competition is Not Economic Competition.
Frontlines 1.
See also the following sources:
Peikoff, Leonard (1991). Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn
Rand. Chapter "Government". Dutton Adult.
Doyle, Kevin (2002). Crypto Anarchy, Cyberstates, and Pirate
Utopias. New York: Lexington Books. pp. 447–448.
Sheehan, Seán M. (2003). Anarchism Reaktion Books. p. 17.
Kelsen, Hans (1988). The Communist Theory of Law. Wm. S. Hein
Publishing. p. 110.
Tellegen, Egbert; Wolsink, Maarten (1998). Society and Its
Environment: an introduction. Routledge. p. 64.
Jones, James (2004). The Merry Month of May. Akashic Books. pp. 37–38.
Sparks, Chris. Isaacs, Stuart (2004). Political Theorists in
Context. Routledge. p. 238.
Bookchin, Murray (2004). Post-Scarcity Anarchism. AK Press. p. 37.
Berkman, Alexander (2005). Life of an Anarchist. Seven Stories
Press. p. 268.
Galleani, Luigi (1925). "The End of Anarchism?". The Anarchist
Library. Retrieved 2 May 2019.
Malatesta, Errico (1924). "Note to the article "Individualism and
Anarchism" by Adamas". The Anarchist Library. Retrieved 2 May 2019.
Tucker, Benjamin. Liberty (129). p. 2.
Martin, James J. (1953). Men Against the State: the State the
Expositors of Individualist Anarchism. Dekalb, Illinois: The Adrian
Allen Associates.
Tucker, Benjamin (1970). Liberty. Greenwood Reprint Corporation.
7–8. p. 26. "Liberty has always insisted that Individualism and
Socialism are not antithetical terms; that, on the contrary, the most
... not of Socialist Anarchism against Individualist Anarchism, but of
Communist Socialism against Individualist Socialism."
McKay, Iain, ed. (2012). "Section G – Is Individualist Anarchism
Capitalistic?". An Anarchist FAQ. Vol. II. Stirling: AK Press. ISBN
9781849351225.
Franks, Benjamin (August 2013). Freeden, Michael; Stears, Marc
(eds.). "Anarchism". The Oxford Handbook of Political Ideologies.
Oxford University Press: 385–404.
doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199585977.013.0001.
Carson, Kevin (2017). "Anarchism and Markets". In Jun, Nathan J.
(2017). Brill's Companion to Anarchism and Philosophy. BRILL. p. 81.
ISBN 9789004356894.
Bakunin, Mikhail. "Works of Mikhail Bakunin 1869". Marxists
Internet Archive. Retrieved 2 April 2018.
Albert, Michael. Anarchism?! Archived 2007-08-17 at the Wayback
Machine. Z Communications. Retrieved 6 September 2006.
"War is the Health of the State". Anarchists see war as an
activity in which the state seeks to gain and consolidate power both
domestically and in foreign lands and subscribe to Randolph Bourne's
view that "war is the health of the state".
"The Failure of Nonviolence"
de Cleyre, Voltairine (1912). Direct Action.
Smith, George H. "The Ethics of Voting". Archived 4 April 2005 at
the Wayback Machine
"J.2 What is direct action?". Archived 27 June 2006 at the Wayback Machine
Peacott, Joe, "Voting Anarchists: An Oxymoron or What?" Archived
2007-08-08 at the Wayback Machine. BAD Broadside #8, Boston Anarchist
Drinking Brigade, 1992; Ward, Colin "The Case Against Voting",
originally published in New Society on 15 May 1987; reprinted in
Freedom, Vol. 48, No. 6, June 1987; "Choose and Lose – The anarchist
case against voting and electoralism" Archived 2007-07-23 at the
Wayback Machine. Infoshop.org.
"Thinking about anarchism – Referendums" Archived 2007-11-09 at
the Wayback Machine. Workers Solidarity No 69, published in March
2002. Retrieved 7 September 2006.
"chomsky.info : The Noam Chomsky Website". chomsky.info. Archived
from the original on 30 September 2015. Retrieved 2 April 2018.
Henley, Jon (30 October 2016). "Iceland elections leave ruling
centre-right party in driving seat". The Guardian. Retrieved 2 April
2018.
Spooner, Lysander, No Treason, no. 2, part 1.
"No Treason". Archived from the original on 4 October 2002.
Retrieved 21 July 2006.
"The Anarchist Vote". Bella Caledonia. 16 September 2014.
Retrieved 19 December 2016.
"Independent and free? A Glasgow anarchist's take on Scottish
independence". Libcom.org. Retrieved 19 December 2016.
"Some quick thoughts on Scottish independence". Libcom.org.
Retrieved 19 December 2016.
"Don't Mourn. Organise. | Edinburgh anarchist statement on the
referendum result". AFed Scotland. 19 September 2014. Retrieved 19
December 2016.
"Appeal to Yes Voters for Direct Action". Edinburgh Anarchist
Federation. Archived from the original on 20 December 2016. Retrieved
19 December 2016.
"14 observations on Brexit and Lexit in the UK EU membership
referendum". Libcom.org. Retrieved 19 December 2016.
"Brexit vote: another sign of global capitalism's deepening
crisis". Libcom.org. Retrieved 19 December 2016.
"Brexit for tanks? The EU and the working class". Libcom.org.
Retrieved 19 December 2016.
"Making sense of the Brexit tide of reaction and the reality of
the racist vote – Andrew Flood". Libcom.org. Retrieved 19 December
2016.
"Brexit means… what? Hapless ideology and practical consequences".
libcom.org. Retrieved 19 December 2016.
"Taking Leave of their senses – What does the Brexit vote mean? –
Mouvement Communiste and Kolektivně proti kapitálu". Libcom.org.
Retrieved 19 December 2016.
Horowitz, Irving Louis (2005). The Anarchists. Aldine Transaction. p. 49.
Bookchin, Murray. The Democratic Dimensions of Anarchism
Bookchin, Murray. "Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An
Unbridgeable Chasm".
Black, Bob. "Anarchy after Leftism". Chapter 5.
Fowler, R. B. The Western Political Quarterly, Vol. 25, No. 4.
(December 1972), pp. 743–744.
"The Revolutionary "Haste". Archived 10 February 2003 at the Wayback Machine
Porter, David, ed. (2006). Vision on Fire: Emma Goldman on the
Spanish Revolution Archived 2013-11-07 at the Wayback Machine. AK
Press. p. 226–228.
"War Is the Health of the State by Randolph Bourne". Struggle.ws.
Retrieved 2 April 2018.
Encyclopedia Britannica,
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Peter-Alekseyevich-Kropotkin
Martin, James J. Men Against the State. p. 220.
The New Freewoman, p. 218.
Meltzer, Albert (2000). Anarchism: Arguments For and Against. AK
Press. p. 50. ISBN 978-1873176573.
"A.3.1 What are the differences between individualist and social
anarchists?". An Anarchist FAQ. Archived 22 September 2008 at the
Wayback Machine
Carson, Kevin. "Mutualist FAQ: Getting There".
Black, Bob (2010). "Nightmares of Reason".
Baginki, Max (May 1907). "Stirner: The Ego and His Own". Mother
Earth (2: 3).
Kropotkin, Peter (1901). "Communism and Anarchy".
"Organisational Platform of the Libertarian Communists" (1926). Dielo Truda.
"My Perspectives". Willful Disobedience (2: 12).
Black, Bob (1974). "Preface to The Right to be Greedy by For
Ourselves" Archived 2009-11-02 at the Wayback Machine.
The Right To Be Greedy: Theses On The Practical Necessity Of
Demanding Everything.
Gross, David. "Theses on Groucho Marxism". Archived from the
original on 5 April 2010. Retrieved 2 November 2009.
Marx, Karl (1875). "Critique of the Gotha Program".
Engels, Friedrich (1875). "Engels to August Bebel In Zwickau".
Geuss, Raymond (2008). Philosophy and Real Politics. pp. 76–80.
Woods, Allen (2014). The Free Development of Each: Studies on
Freedom, Right, and Ethics in Classical German Philosophy. "Marx on
Equality". pp. 253, 266.
Nielsen, Kai (August 1987). "Rejecting Egalitarianism". Political
Theory (15: 3). pp. 411–423.
Marx 1991, p. 959.
Marx 1990, p. 739.
Marx 1993, p. 158, p. 162.
"Anarcho-Feminism – Two Statements – Who we are: An
Anarcho-Feminist Manifesto". Archived 11 October 2006 at the Wayback
Machine
Marsh, Margaret S. Anarchist Women, 1870–1920. Philadelphia:
Temple University Press, 1981.
Marshall, p. 409.
Intimate, p. 94.
Presley, 1979.
Presley, Sharon (18 February 2000). "Libertarian Feminist Heritage
Series: Voltairine de Cleyre". Anarchy Archives. Retrieved 17 December
2016.
Falk 2003, p. 195.
O'Carroll, Aileen. "Mujeres Libres: Women anarchists in the
Spanish Revolution". Workers Solidarity. Archived from the original on
26 September 2015. Retrieved 27 September 2005.
Ribeiro, Pedro. Senzala or Quilombo: Reflections on APOC and the
fate of Black Anarchism.
"Black Anarchism". Anarchist Panther. Archived 13 March 2008 at
the Wayback Machine
@narchist Panther Zine (October 1999). 1st ed. Vol. 1.
Samudzi, Zoé; Anderson, William C.; Kaba, Mariame (5 June 2018).
As Black As Resistance: Finding the Conditions for Liberation. Chico,
California: AK Press. ISBN 9781849353168.
Schapiro, J. Salwyn (1945). "Pierre Joseph Proudhon, Harbinger of
Fascism". American Historical Review. The American Historical Review,
Vol. 50, No. 4. 50 (4): 714–737. doi:10.2307/1842699. JSTOR 1842699.
Bakunin quoted by Shlomo Avineri in Radical Theology, the New
Left, and Israel, p. 245–246. "An article in Auschwitz. Beginning of a
New Era? Reflections on the Holocaust", edited by Eva Fleishner, KTAV
Publishing House, Inc.; The Cathedral Church of St. John Divine;
Anti-Defamation League of B'nai B'rith, 1977, p. 241–254.
Ghadar Movement: Ideology, Organisation and Strategy, Harish K.
Puri, Guru Nanak Dev University Press, Amritsar: "The only account of
Hardayal's short stay in that island Martinique, comes from Bhai
Parmanand, a self exiled Arya Samajist missionary from Lahore, who
stayed a month with him there. Har Dayal used that time, says
Parmanand, to discuss plans to found a new religion: his model was the
Buddha. He ate mostly boiled grain, slept on the bare floor and spent
his time in meditation in a secluded place. Guy Aldred, a famous
English radical and friend, tells us of Hardayal's proclaimed belief
at that time in the coming republic "which was to be a Church, a
religious confraternity ... its motto was to be: atheism,
cosmopolitanism and moral law' Parmamand says that Har Dayal acceded
to his persuasion to go to the USA and decided to make New York a
centre for the propagation of the ancient culture of the Aryan." (p.
55) and "the ideal social order would be the one which approximated to
the legendary Vedic period of Indian history because, as Har Dayal
affirmed, practical equality existed only in that society, where there
were no governors and no governed, no priests and no laymen, no rich
and no poor." (p. 112), referencing The Social Conquest of the Hindu
Race and Meaning of Equality.
"Anarchist Orientalism and the Muslim Community in Britain".
Retrieved 3 May 2007.
Fernandez, Frank (2001). Cuban Anarchism: The History of a
Movement. See Sharp Press. p. 6.
Anarchism, p. 158.
Morris, Brian, Anthropology and Anarchism, "Anarchy: A Journal of
Desire Armed" (no. 45); Mckay, Iain, The legacy of Voltairine De
Cleyre, Anarcho-Syndicalist Review, no. 44; L. Susan Brown, The
Politics of Individualism.
McKay, Iain; et al. (21 January 2010). "Section F – Is
"anarcho"-capitalism a type of anarchism?". An Anarchist FAQ.
Infoshop.org. Archived from the original on 5 December 2011. Retrieved
3 December 2011.
Cheyney, Ryan C. (November 1980). "Social Justice and the Right to
the Labor Product". Political Theory (8: 4). p. 506.
"Individual Liberty: Labor and Its Pay". Archived from the
original on 7 April 2005. Retrieved 11 August 2005.
Bottomore, Tom (1991). "Anarchism". A Dictionary of Marxist
Thought. Oxford: Blackwell Reference. p. 21. ISBN 0-63118082-6.
Outhwaite, William. The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social
Thought, Anarchism entry, Blackwell Publishing, 2003, p. 13: "Their
successors today, such as Murray Rothbard, having abandoned the labor
theory of value, describe themselves as anarcho-capitalists".
See the following sources:
Bullosk, Alan; Trombley, Stephen (ed.) (1999). The Norton
Dictionary of Modern Thought. W. W. Norton & Company. p. 30.
Barry, Norman (2000). Modern Political Theory. Palgrave, p. 70.
Adams, Ian (2002). Political Ideology Today. Manchester
University Press. ISBN 0-7190-6020-6, p. 135.
Grant, Moyra (2003). Key Ideas in Politics. Nelson Thomas. p.
91. ISBN 0-7487-7096-8.
Heider, Ulrike (1994). Anarchism: Left, Right, and Green. City
Lights. p. 3.
Avrich, Paul (1996). Anarchist Voices: An Oral History of
Anarchism in America. Abridged paperback edition. p. 282.
Tormey, Simon (2004). Anti-Capitalism, One World. pp. 118–119.
Raico, Ralph (2004). Authentic German Liberalism of the 19th
Century. École Polytechnique, Centre de Recherche en Épistémologie
Appliquée, Unité associée au CNRS.
Busky, Donald (2000). Democratic Socialism: A Global Survey.
Praeger/Greenwood. p. 4.
Heywood, Andrew (2002). Politics: Second Edition. Palgrave. p. 61.
Offer, John (2000). Herbert Spencer: Critical Assessments.
Routledge. p. 243.
Brown, Susan Love, The Free Market as Salvation from Government:
The Anarcho-Capitalist View, Meanings of the Market: The Free Market
in Western Culture, edited by James G. Carrier, Berg/Oxford, 1997, p.
107 and p. 104)
James J. Martin. Men against the State. p. 208.
Madison, Charles A. (1945). "Anarchism in the United States".
Journal of the History of Ideas. 6 (1): 46–66. doi:10.2307/2707055.
JSTOR 2707055.
Madison, Charles A. (1943). "Benjamin R. Tucker: Individualist and
Anarchist". New England Quarterly. The New England Quarterly, Vol. 16,
No. 3. 16 (3): 444–467. doi:10.2307/361029. JSTOR 361029.
Non-capitalist market anarchists support private possession along
Warren's, Proudhon's, or similar lines. In contrast,
anarcho-capitalists support private property along Lockean or similar
lines.
As Peter Marshall notes in his history of anarchism, "few
anarchists would accept the 'anarcho-capitalists' into the anarchist
camp since they do not share a concern for economic equality and
social justice." Demanding the Impossible, p. 565.
Busky, Donald F. (1 January 2000). Democratic Socialism: A Global
Survey. Greenwood Publishing Group. p. 2. ISBN 9780275968861. "The
same may be said of anarchism: social anarchism—a nonstate form of
socialism—may be distinguished from the nonsocialist, and, in some
cases, procapitalist school of individualist anarchism."
Byldun, Per (19 March 2019). "The Trouble With Socialist
Anarchism". Mises Institute. Retrieved 31 March 2019.
Rothbard, Murray. "Are Libertarians 'Anarchists'?". LewRockwell.com.
Peter Marshall, Demanding the Impossible; John Clark, The
Anarchist Moment; Albert Meltzer, Anarchism: Arguments for and
Against; Noam Chomsky, Understanding Power, David Weick, Anarchist
Justice; Brian Morris, "Anthropology and Anarchism," Anarchy: A
Journal of Desire Armed (no. 45); Peter Sabatini, Libertarianism:
Bogus Anarchy; Donald Rooum, What is Anarchism?; Bob Black,
Libertarian as Conservative
1) Perlin, Terry M. Contemporary Anarchism. Transaction Books, New
Brunswick, NJ 1979, p. 7. 2) Sylvan, Richard. Anarchism. A Companion
to Contemporary Political Philosophy, editors Goodin, Robert E. and
Pettit, Philip. Blackwell Publishing, 1995, p.231.
Chartier, Gary (2009). Economic Justice and Natural Law.
Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.
Carson, Kevin A. (2008). Organization Theory: A Libertarian
Perspective. Charleston, SC:BookSurge.
Carson, Kevin A. (2010). The Homebrew Industrial Revolution: A
Low-Overhead Manifesto. Charleston, SC: BookSurge.
Long, Roderick T. (2000). Reason and Value: Aristotle versus Rand.
Washington, DC:Objectivist Center
Long, Roderick T. (2008). "An Interview With Roderick Long"
Johnson, Charles W. (2008). "Liberty, Equality, Solidarity: Toward
a Dialectical Anarchism." Anarchism/Minarchism: Is a Government Part
of a Free Country? In Long, Roderick T. and Machan, Tibor Aldershot:
Ashgate pp. 155–88.
Richman, Sheldon (23 June 2010). "Why Left-Libertarian?" The
Freeman. Foundation for Economic Education.
Richman, Sheldon (18 December 2009). "Workers of the World Unite
for a Free Market" Archived 22 July 2014 at the Wayback Machine."
Foundation for Economic Education.
Sheldon Richman (3 February 2011). "Libertarian Left: Free-market
anti-capitalism, the unknown ideal Archived 2012-05-09 at the Wayback
Machine." The American Conservative. Retrieved 5 March 2012.
Sciabarra, Chris Matthew (2000). Total Freedom: Toward a
Dialectical Libertarianism. University Park, PA:Pennsylvania State
University Press.
See Gary Chartier, "Advocates of Freed Markets Should Oppose
Capitalism," "Free-Market Anti-Capitalism?" session, annual
conference, Association of Private Enterprise Education (Cæsar's
Palace, Las Vegas, NV, April 13, 2010); Gary Chartier, "Advocates of
Freed Markets Should Embrace 'Anti-Capitalism'"; Gary Chartier,
Socialist Ends, Market Means: Five Essays. Cp. Tucker, "Socialism."
Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. (2011). Markets Not
Capitalism: Individualist Anarchism Against Bosses, Inequality,
Corporate Power, and Structural Poverty. Brooklyn, NY:Minor
Compositions/Autonomedia. pp. 1–16.
Gillis, William (2011). "The Freed Market." In Chartier, Gary and
Johnson, Charles. Markets Not Capitalism. Brooklyn, NY: Minor
Compositions/Autonomedia. pp. 19–20.
Gary Chartier and Charles W. Johnson (eds). Markets Not
Capitalism: Individualist Anarchism Against Bosses, Inequality,
Corporate Power, and Structural Poverty. Minor Compositions; 1st
edition (November 5, 2011
Liebknecht, Wilhelm (1896). "Our Recent Congress". Justice.
Retrieved 31 May 2007.
Gouldner, A. W. (November 1982). "Marx's Last Battle: Bakunin and
the First International". Theory and Society. (11: 6). pp. 853–884.
Gouldner argues that Bakunin formulated an original critique of
Marxism as "the ideology, not of the working class, but of a new class
of scientific intelligentsia—who would corrupt socialism, make
themselves a new elite, and impose their rule on the majority" (pp.
860–861).
Slavic Review (50: 1) (Spring 1991). pp. 127–143.
Bottomore, Thomas B. (1964). Elites and Society p. 54.
Shatz, Marshall S. "Jan Waclaw Machajski: A Radical Critic Of The
Russian Intelligentsia And Socialism". Archived from the original on
26 October 2009. Retrieved 26 October 2009.
Fox, Michael S. "Ante Ciliga, Trotskii and State Capitalism:
Theory, Tactics and Reevaluation during the Purge Era, 1935–1939"
(PDF). Archived from the original on 27 October 2009. Retrieved 27
October 2009.
"Why is state socialism just state capitalism?". Archived 19
December 2009 at the Wayback Machine
Makdisi, Saree; Casarino, Cesare; Karl, Rebecca E. (1996). Marxism
Beyond Marxism. Routledge. p. 198.
Sayers, Sean (1998). Marxism and Human Nature. Routledge. p. 105.
"L'Angleterre a-t-elle l'heureux privilège de n'avoir ni
Agioteurs, ni Banquiers, ni Faiseurs de services, ni Capitalistes ?".
In Clavier, Étienne (1788). De la foi publique envers les créanciers
de l'état : lettres à M. Linguet sur le n° CXVI de ses annales (in
French). p. 19.
Braudel, Fernand (1979). The Wheels of Commerce: Civilization and
Capitalism 15th–18th Century. Harper and Row.
Hodgson, Geoffrey (2015). Conceptualizing Capitalism:
Institutions, Evolution, Future. University of Chicago Press. p. 252.
Popper, Karl (1994). The Open Society and Its Enemies. Routledge
Classics. ISBN 978-0-415-61021-6.
McElroy, Wendy (1995). "Intellectual Property: The Late Nineteenth
Century Libertarian Debate". Libertarian Heritage (14). ISBN
1-85637-281-2. Retrieved 24 June 2005.
Birch, Paul (1998). "Anarcho-capitalism Dissolves Into City
States" (PDF). Libertarian Alliance. Legal Notes. no. 28: 4. ISSN
0267-7083. Retrieved 5 July 2010.
Nick Manley (7 May 2014). "Brief Introduction To Left-Wing Laissez
Faire Economic Theory: Part One". Center for a Stateless Society.
Retrieved 23 April 2019.
Nick Maley (9 May 2014). "Brief Introduction To Left-Wing Laissez
Faire Economic Theory: Part Two". Center for a Stateless Society
Retrieved 29 April 2019.
"Advocates of Freed Markets Should Embrace "Anti-Capitalism".
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph (1840). What is Property? Or, an Inquiry
into the Principle of Right and of Government.
Friedland, William H.; Rosberg, Carl G. (1965). African Socialism.
Stanford University Press. p. 25. ISBN 978-0804702034.
"B.3 Why are anarchists against private property?". An Anarchist
FAQ. Archived from the original on 14 November 2017. Retrieved 29
April 2018.
"End Private Property, Not Kenny Loggins". Jacobin. Archived from
the original on 26 October 2017. Retrieved 29 April 2018.
"Reclaim the Streets" Donnacha DeLong, RTÉ News Online 2002.
Retrieved 5 September 2006.
"The New Anarchists", Graeber, David, New Left Review 13,
January–February 2002. Retrieved 6 September 2006.
"G8 Summit – J18: Global Carnival Against Corporate Tyranny,
London, England", C. L. Staten, EmergencyNet News journalist, writing
for RTÉ's website in 2002. Retrieved 5 September 2006
"May Day demonstrations: Who's who". BBC NEWS. 2003-04-28.
Retrieved 2020-04-02.
"Anarchism as a Scapegoat of the 21st century: violence, anarchism
and anti-globalisation protests" Archived 2007-10-21 at the Wayback
Machine, Thrall issue #21, 2001. Retrieved 5 September 2006.
Paul, Ellen Frankel. Miller, Fred Dycus. Paul, Jeffrey. 1993. (no
title listed) Cambridge University Press. p. 115.
Chomsky, Noam (2003). Chomsky on Democracy & Education. Routledge. p. 398.
Chomsky, Noam. Language and Politics. AK Press. p. 153.
Peacock, Adrian. 1999. Two Hundred Pharaohs, Five Billion Slaves.
Ellipsis London.
Goodwin, Barbara (2007). Using Political Ideas. John Wiley & Sons.
Brooks, Thom (2002). Book Reviews. Journal of Applied Philosophy.
19 (1). 75–90. doi:10.1111/1468-5930.00206.
McKay, Iain (2007). "Section F.7.3 - Can there be a 'right-wing'
anarchism?". An Anarchist FAQ, Volume I. AK Press. ISBN
978-1-902593-90-6. Archived from the original on 28 January 2012.
McKay, Iain; et al. (21 January 2010). "Section F.7.3 - Can there
be a 'right-wing' anarchism?". An Anarchist FAQ. Infoshop.org.
Archived from the original on 17 November 2011. Retrieved 21 January
2012.
McKay, Iain (2007). "Section D.6 - Are anarchists against
Nationalism?". An Anarchist FAQ, Volume I. AK Press. ISBN
978-1-902593-90-6. Archived from the original on 28 January 2012.
McKay, Iain; et al. (21 January 2010). "Section D.6 - Are
anarchists against Nationalism?". An Anarchist FAQ. Infoshop.org.
Archived from the original on 3 March 2012. Retrieved 22 January 2012.
Heider, Ulrike. Anarchism: Left, Right and Green. San Francisco:
City Lights Books. 1994.
Griffin 2003; Goodrick-Clarke 2003; Macklin 2005; Sykes 2005;
Sunshine 2008; Sanchez 2009.
"Precarity, or Why 69 is Pink (w/Mondo Foti!)". Daily Kos.
Retrieved 3 May 2007.
Firth, Will. "Esperanto kaj anarkiismo". "Anarkiistoj estis inter
la pioniroj de la disvastigo de Esperanto. En 1905 fondiĝis en
Stokholmo la unua anarkiisma Esperanto-grupo. Sekvis multaj aliaj: en
Bulgario, Ĉinio kaj aliaj landoj. Anarkiistoj kaj
anarki-sindikatistoj, kiuj antaŭ la Unua Mondmilito apartenis al la
nombre plej granda grupo inter la proletaj esperantistoj, fondis en
1906 la internacian ligon Paco-Libereco, kiu eldonis la Internacian
Socian Revuon. Paco-libereco unuiĝis en 1910 kun alia progresema
asocio, Esperantista Laboristaro. La komuna organizaĵo nomiĝis
Liberiga Stelo. Ĝis 1914 tiu organizaĵo eldonis multe da revolucia
literaturo en Esperanto, interalie ankaŭ anarkiisma. Tial povis evolui
en la jaroj antaŭ la Unua Mondmilito ekzemple vigla korespondado inter
eŭropaj kaj japanaj anarkiistoj. En 1907 la Internacia Anarkiisma
Kongreso en Amsterdamo faris rezolucion pri la afero de internacia
lingvo, kaj venis dum la postaj jaroj similaj kongresaj rezolucioj.
Esperantistoj, kiuj partoprenis tiujn kongresojn, okupiĝis precipe pri
la internaciaj rilatoj de la anarkiistoj".
"El Movimiento naturista". Archived from the original on 20 March
2012. Retrieved 3 June 2014. "Proliferarán así diversos grupos que
practicarán el excursionismo, el naturismo, el nudismo, la
emancipación sexual o el esperantismo, alrededor de asociaciones
informales vinculadas de una manera o de otra al anarquismo.
Precisamente las limitaciones a las asociaciones obreras impuestas
desde la legislación especial de la Dictadura potenciarán
indirectamente esta especie de asociacionismo informal en que
confluirá el movimiento anarquista con esta heterogeneidad de
prácticas y tendencias. Uno de los grupos más destacados, que será el
impulsor de la revista individualista Ética será el Ateneo Naturista
Ecléctico, con sede en Barcelona, con sus diferentes secciones la más
destacada de las cuales será el grupo excursionista Sol y Vida."; "La
insumisión voluntaria. El anarquismo individualista español durante la
Dictadura y la Segunda República (1923–1938)" (PDF). Archived from the
original (PDF) on 18 June 2013. Retrieved 6 May 2011.
del Barrio, Toño; Lins, Ulrich. La utilización del esperanto
durante la Guerra Civil Española. Paper for the International Congress
on the Spanish Civil War (Madrid, 27–29 November 2006).
Griffin 2003.
Goodrick-Clarke 2003.
Macklin 2005.
Sykes 2005.
Sunshine 2008.
Sanchez 2009.
Afedscotland (18 September 2014). "Referendum rant from an
immigrant". AFed Scotland. Retrieved 19 December 2016.
"The SNP, Scottish Nationalism, and the Class Struggle: Yesterday,
Today, and Tomorrow". AFed Scotland. Archived from the original on 20
December 2016. Retrieved 19 December 2016.
Harper, Clifford, ed. (1994). Prolegomena: To a Study of the
Return of the Repressed in History. London: Rebel Press. ISBN
0-946061-13-0.
"Post anarchist clearing house".
Kropotkin, Peter, "Communism and Anarchy" Archived 2005-10-20 at
the Wayback Machine.
Liberty (Not the Daughter but the Mother of Order) (1881–1908); 3
September 1881; 1, 3; APS Online, p. 3; Tucker uses the terms
"voluntary" and "compulsory" communisms. Some market anarchists reject
the distinction.
"Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph" (2006). Encyclopædia Britannica.
Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. "What Is Property?" ISBN 1-4191-9353-8 p. 221.
Quoted in Paul Thomas, Karl Marx and the Anarchists, Routledge
(1980), p. 303.
Maximov, G. P., ed. (1953).The Political Philosophy of Bakunin.
New York: The Free Press. p. 269.
Madison, Charles A. "Anarchism in the United States". Journal of
the History of Ideas, Vol 6, No 1, January 1945, p. 56.
Marx, Karl (1846). The German Ideology. "It follows from all we
have been saying up till now that the communal relationship into which
the individuals of a class entered, and which was determined by their
common interests over against a third party, was always a community to
which these individuals belonged only as average individuals, only
insofar as they lived within the conditions of existence of their
class — a relationship in which they participated not as individuals
but as members of a class. With the community of revolutionary
proletarians, on the other hand, who take their conditions of
existence [...] under their control, it is just the reverse; it is as
individuals that the individuals participate in it. [...] Communism
differs from all previous movements in that it overturns the basis of
all earlier relations of production and intercourse, and for the first
time consciously treats all natural premises as the creatures of
hitherto existing men, strips them of their natural character and
subjugates them to the power of the united individuals. Its
organization is, therefore, essentially economic, the material
production of the conditions of this unity; it turns existing
conditions into conditions of unity. The reality, which communism is
creating, is precisely the true basis for rendering it impossible that
anything should exist independently of individuals, insofar as reality
is only a product of the preceding intercourse of individuals
themselves".
Marx, Karl (1848). The Communist Manifesto. "Chapther II.
Proletarians and Communists".
Marx, Karl (1894). Capital, Volume III. "Part VII. Revenues and
their Sources".
For instance, Benjamin Tucker says: "Yes, genuine Anarchism is
consistent Manchesterism, and Communistic or pseudo-Anarchism is
inconsistent Manchesterism". Tucker, Benjamin. "Labor and Its Pay".
Archived 2005-04-07 at the Wayback Machine. From Individual Liberty:
selections from the writings of Benjamin T. Tucker); Victor Yarros
says: "There is no logical justification, no rational explanation, and
no scientific reasoning has been, is, will be, or can be advanced in
defence of that unimaginable impossibility, Communistic Anarchism".
Yarros, Victor S. "A Princely Paradox". Archived 27 September 2007 at
the Wayback Machine. Liberty. Vol 4. No. 19. Saturday, 9 April 1887,
whole number 97. Henry Appleton says: "All Communism, under whatever
guise, is the natural enemy of Anarchism, and a Communist sailing
under the flag of Anarchism is as false a figure as could be
invented". Appleton, Henry. "Anarchism, True and False". Liberty 2.24.
no. 50. 6 September 1884. p. 4.; Clarence Lee Swartz says: "One of the
tests of any reform movement with regard to personal liberty is this:
Will the movement prohibit or abolish private property? If it does, it
is an enemy of liberty. For one of the most important criteria of
freedom is the right to private property in the products of ones
labor. State Socialists, Communists, Syndicalists and
Communist-Anarchists deny private property". Swartz, Clarence Lee.
"What is Mutualism?".
Brooks, Frank H. (ed) (1994) The Individualist Anarchists: An
Anthology of Liberty (1881–1908), Transaction Publishers, p. 76.
Appleton, Henry. "The Boston Anarchists". Archived 2005-12-14 at
the Wayback Machine. Liberty, Vol. 4, No. 3, May 26, 1886, Whole No.
81.
"What is Ideology?" by Jason McQuinn
Bey, Hakim (1994). Immediatism. AK Press. p. 4. Archived 5
December 2009 at the Wayback Machine
"An esoteric interpretation of the I.W.W. preamble". The Anarchist
Library. Archived from the original on 7 October 2011. Retrieved 3
October 2011.
Bakunin, Mikhail (1971) [5 October 1872]. "Letter to La Liberté".
In Dolgoff, Sam (ed.). Bakunin on Anarchy. Translated by Dolgoff, Sam.
Retrieved 8 September 2009 – via Marxists Internet Archive.
Woodcock, George (1975) [1962]. Anarchism. Harmondsworth, England:
Penguin Books. p. 158. ISBN 0-14-020622-1..
Bakunin, Mikhail (1973). Lehning, Arthur (ed.). Michael Bakunin:
Selected Writings (PDF). Evergreen. pp. 191–192. ISBN 0-224-00893-5.
Archived from the original (PDF) on 3 August 2020.
Robertson, Ann. "Marxism and Anarchism: The Philosophical Roots of
the Marx-Bakunin Conflict – Part Two" (PDF). Workerscompass.org.
Retrieved 1 April 2018.
Thoburn, Nicholas (2003). "The Lumpenproletariat and the
Proletarian Unnamable". Deleuze, Marx and Politics. Routledge. ISBN
9780415753845.
Bakunin, Mikhail (1971) [1873]. "Statism and Anarchy". In Dolgoff,
Sam (ed.). Bakunin on Anarchy. Translated by Dolgoff, Sam. Retrieved 8
September 2009 – via Marxists Internet Archive.
Engels, Friedrich (1978) [1874]. "On Authority". In Tucker, Robert
C. (ed.). The Marx-Engels reader (2nd ed.). New York: Norton. ISBN
978-0-393-05684-6. LCCN 77016635. OCLC 318414641. Retrieved 18 March
2019 – via Marxists Internet Archive.
Sperber, Jonathan (2013). Karl Marx: A Nineteenth-Century Life.
W.W. Norton & Co. ISBN 9780871403544.
"Казарменный коммунизм" [Barracks Communism]. Great Soviet
Encyclopedia (in Russian).
Duncan, Graeme Campbell (December 1976). Marx and Mill: Two Views
of Social Conflict and Social Harmony. Cambridge University Press. p.
194. ISBN 9780521291309.
Lenin, Vladimir (2001). Marxism versus Anarchism. Resistance
Books. p. 88. ISBN 9781876646035.
Glavnyye osnovy budushchego obshchestvennogo stroya (Главные
основы будущего общественного строя). According to Marx, it was
printed in the second issue of Narodnaya rasprava available in Geneva
in December 1869, but it was labelled "St.Petersburg, winter 1870".
McClellan, Woodford (1973). "Nechaevshchina: An Unknown Chapter".
Slavic Review. 32 (3): 546–553. doi:10.2307/2495409. ISSN 0037-6779.
JSTOR 2495409.
Mayer, Robert (1993). "Lenin and the Concept of the Professional
Revolutionary". History of Political Thought. 14 (2): 249–263. ISSN
0143-781X. JSTOR 26214357.
"The Influences of Chernyshevsky, Tkachev, and Nechaev on the
political thought of V.I. Lenin". Retrieved 25 March 2019.
"Сергей Нечаев: "темный чуланчик" русской революции" [Sergei
Nechaev: the "dark closet" of the Russian revolution]. МирТесен –
рекомендательная социальная сеть (in Russian). Retrieved 25 March
2019.
Kimball, Alan (1973). "The First International and the Russian
Obshchina". Slavic Review. 32 (3): 491–514. doi:10.2307/2495406. ISSN
0037-6779. JSTOR 2495406. S2CID 164131867.
Read, Christopher (2005). Lenin: A Revolutionary Life. London:
Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-20649-5.
Busgalin, Alexander; Mayer, Günter (2008). "Kasernenkommunismus".
Historisch-kritisches Wörterbuch des Marxismus. 7: I. Spalten. pp.
407–411 (PDF text)
Gorter, Herman; Pannekok, Anton; Pankhurst, Sylvia; Ruhl, Otto
(2007). Non-Leninist Marxism: Writings on the Workers Councils. Red
and Black.
Screpanti, Ernesto (2007). Libertarian Communism: Marx Engels and
the Political Economy of Freedom. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Draper, Hal (1971). "The Principle of Self-Emancipation in Marx
and Engels". Archived 23 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine Socialist
Register (4).
Chomsky, Noam. "Government In The Future". Archived 21 November
2010 at the Wayback Machine Lecture at the Poetry Center of the New
York YM-YWHA.
Further reading
Gordon, Uri (2007). Anarchy Alive!: Anti-Authoritarian Politics
from Practice to Theory. Sydney: Pluto Press. ISBN 978-0-7453-2683-2.
OCLC 154769337.
Gordon, Uri (2007). "Anarchism and Political Theory: Contemporary
Problems". The Anarchist Library. Retrieved 4 May 2019.
Kerl, Eric (July–August 2010). "Contemporary anarchism".
International Socialist Review (72). Retrieved 4 May 2019.
External links
Media related to Issues in anarchism at Wikimedia Commons
External links modified
Hello fellow Wikipedians,
I have just modified 6 external links on Issues in anarchism. Please
take a moment to review my edit. If you have any questions, or need
the bot to ignore the links, or the page altogether, please visit this
simple FaQ for additional information. I made the following changes:
Corrected formatting/usage for http://www.britannica.com/eb/article-9117285
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20120105095946/http://www.iaf-ifa.org/principle…
to http://www.iaf-ifa.org/principles/english.html
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20120314184800/http://www.anarchistsurvey.com/r…
to http://www.anarchistsurvey.com/results/
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20130928043924/http://www.chomsky.info/intervie…
to http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/1991----02.htm
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20021004072643/http://www.lysanderspooner.org/n…
to http://www.lysanderspooner.org/notreason.htm
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20080922025342/http://www.infoshop.org/faq/secA…
to http://www.infoshop.org/faq/secA3.html
When you have finished reviewing my changes, you may follow the
instructions on the template below to fix any issues with the URLs.
This message was posted before February 2018. After February 2018,
"External links modified" talk page sections are no longer generated
or monitored by InternetArchiveBot. No special action is required
regarding these talk page notices, other than regular verification
using the archive tool instructions below. Editors have permission to
delete these "External links modified" talk page sections if they want
to de-clutter talk pages, but see the RfC before doing mass systematic
removals. This message is updated dynamically through the template
{{source check}} (last update: 18 January 2022).
If you have discovered URLs which were erroneously considered dead
by the bot, you can report them with this tool.
If you found an error with any archives or the URLs themselves,
you can fix them with this tool.
Cheers.—InternetArchiveBot (Report bug) 18:04, 15 April 2017 (UTC)[reply]
External links modified
Hello fellow Wikipedians,
I have just modified one external link on Issues in anarchism. Please
take a moment to review my edit. If you have any questions, or need
the bot to ignore the links, or the page altogether, please visit this
simple FaQ for additional information. I made the following changes:
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20051214233855/http://www.againstpolitics.com/m…
to http://www.againstpolitics.com/market_anarchism/appleton_boston.htm
When you have finished reviewing my changes, you may follow the
instructions on the template below to fix any issues with the URLs.
This message was posted before February 2018. After February 2018,
"External links modified" talk page sections are no longer generated
or monitored by InternetArchiveBot. No special action is required
regarding these talk page notices, other than regular verification
using the archive tool instructions below. Editors have permission to
delete these "External links modified" talk page sections if they want
to de-clutter talk pages, but see the RfC before doing mass systematic
removals. This message is updated dynamically through the template
{{source check}} (last update: 18 January 2022).
If you have discovered URLs which were erroneously considered dead
by the bot, you can report them with this tool.
If you found an error with any archives or the URLs themselves,
you can fix them with this tool.
Cheers.—InternetArchiveBot (Report bug) 21:41, 4 June 2017 (UTC)[reply]
External links modified
Hello fellow Wikipedians,
I have just modified 5 external links on Issues in anarchism. Please
take a moment to review my edit. If you have any questions, or need
the bot to ignore the links, or the page altogether, please visit this
simple FaQ for additional information. I made the following changes:
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20070516094548/http://www.theglobeandmail.com/s…
to https://www.theglobeandmail.com/servlet/story/RTGAM.20070514.wxlanarchist14…
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20060627215135/http://www.infoshop.org/faq/secJ…
to http://www.infoshop.org/faq/secJ2.html
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20030210201006/http://flag.blackened.net/revolt…
to http://flag.blackened.net/revolt/anarchists/malatesta/rev_haste.html
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20061011013823/http://www.anarcha.org/sallydari…
to http://www.anarcha.org/sallydarity/Anarcho-FeminismTwoStatements.htm
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/web/20050407014846/http://flag.blackened.net/daver/…
to http://flag.blackened.net/daver/anarchism/tucker/tucker37.html
When you have finished reviewing my changes, you may follow the
instructions on the template below to fix any issues with the URLs.
This message was posted before February 2018. After February 2018,
"External links modified" talk page sections are no longer generated
or monitored by InternetArchiveBot. No special action is required
regarding these talk page notices, other than regular verification
using the archive tool instructions below. Editors have permission to
delete these "External links modified" talk page sections if they want
to de-clutter talk pages, but see the RfC before doing mass systematic
removals. This message is updated dynamically through the template
{{source check}} (last update: 18 January 2022).
If you have discovered URLs which were erroneously considered dead
by the bot, you can report them with this tool.
If you found an error with any archives or the URLs themselves,
you can fix them with this tool.
Cheers.—InternetArchiveBot (Report bug) 19:02, 17 November 2017 (UTC)[reply]
Talk:Issues in anarchism/Archive 1
>From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
< Talk:Issues in anarchism
Jump to navigation Jump to search
This is an archive of past discussions. Do not edit the contents of
this page. If you wish to start a new discussion or revive an old one,
please do so on the current talk page.
Archive 1
Contents
1 Appears to contradict article Patriarchy
2 It's probably just me
3 Merge?
4 Proposed merge from definitional concerns in anarchist theory
4.1 Leftover material from merge
5 Really repetitive line
6 Messed up
7 Zaxlebax: Undue Weight
8 External links modified
Appears to contradict article Patriarchy
I have tagged this article because it appears to contradict something
stated in Patriarchy. Please see the discussion on that article's talk
page for full details, and reply there if you want to comment.
Thanks.—greenrd 18:51, 28 March 2007 (UTC)[reply]
It's probably just me
But Anarcho-Capitalism? To quote the internet: "WTF?" —Preceding
unsigned comment added by 142.162.198.171 (talk) 17:19, 14 September
2007 (UTC)[reply]
Merge?
Sounds like a good idea. I was about to propose the same. Jacob Haller
16:41, 19 September 2007 (UTC)[reply]
Note to anarcho-wikipedian otaku for historical posterity: the
merge referred to is Major conflicts within anarchist thought to this
article. Skomorokh incite 23:54, 13 December 2007 (UTC)[reply]
Proposed merge from definitional concerns in anarchist theory
Definitional concerns can uncontroversially be said to be issues in
anarchism; the question I am posing is whether it is better to give
definitional concerns in anarchist theory it's own article, or to make
it a major section of this article. The main issue, I think, is that
that article is far from comprehensive; it has a lede of acceptable
length and a rather good section on the Zaxlebax problem, but the
remainder of the article is made up of stub sections. I favour merging
all non-discrete underdeveloped articles on aspects of one topic into
a single article, beating that article into shape, and then
re-splitting sections into their own articles as appropriate once they
become fully developed. Isolated articles have too few eyes on them
and tend to be the forgotten projects of a small handful of editors,
whereas articles like Anarchism for example are frequently revised and
updated. Please indicate your support or opposition to the proposed
merge here. Skomorokh incite 14:27, 13 January 2008 (UTC)[reply]
Support, I think it is a good idea to merge these two articles
creating a Definitional concerns section in the Issues in anarchism
article. The Definitional concerns in anarchist theory may be a
remnant of the Anarchist POV wars as it seems to be intended to
clarify the terminological fallacies and misunderstandings. Lord
Metroid (talk) 15:57, 13 January 2008 (UTC)[reply]
Support. definitional concerns in anarchist theory was a way to
address substantive terminological issues which editors were gaming to
impose particular POVs on articles. The issues there need to be
addressed somewhere, but, as these definitional issues are, in fact,
current issues for the movement, this page seems to be a fine place to
address them. Libertatia (talk) 19:08, 13 January 2008 (UTC)[reply]
Glad to see we are in agreement; I'm going to go ahead and
merge the articles, with Definitional concerns as the first subsection
of this article Skomorokh incite 22:55, 17 January 2008 (UTC)[reply]
Leftover material from merge
The following is unused content from the now-merged definitional
concerns in anarchist theory. If you can think of an appropriate place
to use this, list of basic anarchism topics perhaps, please feel free.
Skomorokh incite 22:55, 17 January 2008 (UTC)[reply]
Many terms can either designate specific forms of anarchism or
broader trends within anarchism. In rough alphabetical order:
"Agorism" can refer to a counter-economic strategies or to
market propertarian left-libertarianism.
In the socialist tradition, "collectivist anarchism" refers to
those forms, outlined by Mikhail Bakunin, among others, which combine
community ownership of most or all of the means of production with
community payment for labor. In certain other traditions,
"collectivist anarchism" refers to social/communal anarchism in
general.
"Communal anarchism" refers to collectivist anarchism,
communist anarchism, and collectivist or communist forms of other
schools (e.g. of anarcho-syndicalism).
"Individualist anarchism" can refer to egoist anarchism or
various forms of market anarchism.
"Social anarchism" most often refers to collectivist
anarchism, communist anarchism, and collectivist or communist forms of
other schools (e.g. of anarcho-syndicalism). It can also refer to the
circle around the periodical "Social Anarchism."
In the socialist tradition, "socialist anarchism" refers to
any form which opposes presently-existing capitalism and consciously
favors a more egalitarian society, e.g. some forms of agorism,
collectivist anarchism, communist anarchism, most forms of mutualist
anarchism. In some other libertarian traditions, "socialist anarchism"
may be limited to non-market forms of socialist anarchism.
"Syndicalism" can refer to labor-union-centered strategies, or
specifically to social anarchist versions of these.
"Voluntary socialism" was Francis D. Tandy's term for his form
of individualist anarchism.
"Distributism" is a Roman Catholic tradition which is
sometimes considered a form of left-libertarianism.
"Industrialism" can refer to any of industrialization (not an
anarchist ideology), a certain classical-liberal tradition, and
industrial unionism.
Really repetitive line
There are two phrases in this article that are nearly identical. The
first, under "Ends and Means" reads
Anarchists have often been portrayed as dangerous and violent,
possibly due to a number of high-profile violent actions, including
riots, assassinations, insurrections, and terrorism committed by some
anarchists as well as persistently negative media portrayals.
The next occurrence, under "Violence and non-violence" goes
Anarchists have often been portrayed as dangerous and violent, due
mainly to a number of high-profile violent acts including riots,
assassinations, and insurrections involving anarchists.
Maybe someone should rewrite one of these sentences? —Preceding
unsigned comment added by 167.1.143.100 (talk) 10:36, 24 March 2008
(UTC)[reply]
Messed up
The following two sentences convey a biased view:
Historically, anarchists considered themselves socialists and opposed
to capitalism. Thus, anarcho-capitalism is considered by many
anarchists today as not being true anarchism.
The terms "socialists" and "capitalism" seem to be used in a modern
way, creating somewhat an opposition between the invidual anarchists,
which seem to be included in the categorial term "anarchists" in the
cited sentence, and the anarcho-capitalists. But that's not true, as
one can truly see by reading the works of Spooner and Tucker cited on
this page. Capitalism unterstood as a model of a free-market
consisting of bargaining individuals free of coercion through states
or the likes of them was in the mind of Spooner and Tucker (just read
the cited paragraphs). So creating a fake opposition between
anarcho-capitalists and individual anarchists is just original
research and pushing an anti-anarcho-capitalist position
The term "socialist" in its historical context is NOT the same as it
is used today, or even compared to the "socialists" of e.g. China or
former Soviet Union. See
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Issues_in_anarchism#The_.22Zaxlebax.22_Problem
Please read these better formulated paragraphs:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Anarchism#Anarcho-capitalism_and_free_market_a…
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Anarchism#Individualist_anarchism
80.121.36.169 (talk) 05:16, 1 July 2008 (UTC)[reply]
Zaxlebax: Undue Weight
Why do we have an entire section devoted to explaining the use of a
term that is not even the subject of the article? It would be better
if we simply summarize the zaxlebax problem in a sentence or two...
"The word anarchism is used in different ways by different people
(what Roderick Long has referred to as the "zaxlebax problem")."
Interested readers can link from there to the full discussion on the
actual article about the zaxlebax problem. Nathan McKnight -- Aelffin
(talk) 05:53, 21 July 2009 (UTC)[reply]
I agree. Also, there are absolutely no secondary sources for this.
I propose that the section be removed. Bob A (talk) 21:21, 9 November
2009 (UTC)[reply]
External links modified
Hello fellow Wikipedians,
I have just added archive links to one external link on Issues in
anarchism. Please take a moment to review my edit. If necessary, add
{{cbignore}} after the link to keep me from modifying it.
Alternatively, you can add {{nobots|deny=InternetArchiveBot}} to keep
me off the page altogether. I made the following changes:
Added archive
https://web.archive.org/20050404190517/http://fuckthevote.org:80/TheEthicso…
to http://fuckthevote.org/TheEthicsofVoting
When you have finished reviewing my changes, please set the checked
parameter below to true to let others know.
This message was posted before February 2018. After February 2018,
"External links modified" talk page sections are no longer generated
or monitored by InternetArchiveBot. No special action is required
regarding these talk page notices, other than regular verification
using the archive tool instructions below. Editors have permission to
delete these "External links modified" talk page sections if they want
to de-clutter talk pages, but see the RfC before doing mass systematic
removals. This message is updated dynamically through the template
{{source check}} (last update: 18 January 2022).
If you have discovered URLs which were erroneously considered dead
by the bot, you can report them with this tool.
If you found an error with any archives or the URLs themselves,
you can fix them with this tool.
Cheers.—cyberbot IITalk to my owner:Online 14:41, 16 January 2016 (UTC)[reply]
1
0

Censorship: Brazil Judicial Party Follows US Democrats Censorbans Sitting President Bolsonaro Off All Social Media
by grarpamp 06 Sep '22
by grarpamp 06 Sep '22
06 Sep '22
Blocking the Brazilian President’s Social Media: Supreme Court’s
Threat to Democracy
Augusto Zimmermann
Augusto Zimmermann
September 5, 2022 Updated: September 5, 2022
biggersmaller
Print
Commentary
In Brazil, some judges have highly ambitious political goals and make
decisions accordingly.
The current presiding justice at the nation’s Supreme Electoral Court
is Alexandre de Moraes. He was elected as the presiding electoral
officer in August, in a public ceremony with 2,000 guests at the court
auditorium. He was a member of the Brazilian Social Democratic Party
before being nominated justice of the nation’s Federal Supreme Court
on Feb. 22, 2017.
Before being nominated to the nation’s highest court, as reported by
the French daily Le Monde, he was at the centre of a controversy when
the daily Estadão published an investigation showing that he had
intervened as a lawyer in at least 123 legal cases to defend a
corporation that some have argued is suspected of being linked to
Brazil’s main drug trafficking group, the First Command of the
Capital.
Moraes, who is now the nation’s top electoral officer in Brazil and
responsible for overseeing the presidential elections, has issued
numerous “monocratic decisions” against “misinformation,” in addition
to sending some of President Jair Bolsonaro’s friends and supporters
to jail, confiscating their electronic devices, and freezing their
bank accounts.
On March 18, for example, Moraes ordered the nationwide suspension of
the messaging app Telegram. The ruling came after Telegram ignored an
earlier order to block the account of Allan dos Santos, a supporter of
Bolsonaro accused of spreading “misinformation.” He had previously
issued a warrant for the arrest of Santos in October.
In his ruling suspending Telegram nationwide, Moraes mentions its
failing to remove “misleading” content from Bolsonaro’s own Telegram
page. As reported, not only did he order the shutdown of the message
app nationwide but also ordered Apple and Google to introduce
“technological obstacles” to block Telegram on their operating systems
and withdraw it from their digital stores in Brazil.
Bolsonaro, who seeks reelection in October, relies on Telegram to
reach his voter base. He has more than a million followers on the
platform and this could prove crucial to his electoral campaign.
Jair Bolsonaro Brazil’s President Jair Bolsonaro speaks, during a
joint press conference with Paraguay’s president at the Planalto
Palace in Brasilia, Brazil, on Nov. 24, 2021. (Raul Spinasse/AP Photo)
‘Authoritarian Decisions’
On March 19, during the popular television program “Os Pingos nos Is”
from Jovem Pam, journalist Augusto Nunes accused Moraes of committing
several illegalities, including the abuse of authority and the
violation of a cláusula pétrea (“stone clause”) in the Brazilian
Constitution that makes freedom of expression an inalienable right of
the citizen.
Nunes also criticized the silence of politicians about Moraes’s
“decisions,” including the banning of Telegram nationwide.
“It’s time to demand senators and judges handcuffed for their
cowardice. And those appointed by President Jair Bolsonaro have to
explain how long this cowardly silence they have maintained in the
face of arrogance will last,” he said.
On May 27, 2020, Justice Moraes, who had become the nation’s top
electoral officer, ordered the federal police to launch an operation
probing businessmen, bloggers, and politicians allied to Bolsonaro. In
the decision that authorised the operation, he also determined the
blocking of all their accounts on social media outlets such as
Facebook, Twitter, and Instagram. According to him, the monocratic
decision is necessary for the interruption of “misinformation” and
“fake news.”
The investigation on “misinformation” conducted by Moraes concerns
more generally the dissemination of information regarding the
transparency of electronic voting machines and the credibility of the
Brazilian electoral commission, which is actually headed by Moraes
himself.
Filipe Martins, the special advisor to the presidency of the Republic
for international affairs, commented that “journalists, humorists, and
ordinary citizens who act spontaneously are being treated as bandits
for daring to express opinions that displease the establishment.”
Bolsanaro Not the Only Target
Among the targets of police actions ordered by Moraes are the national
president of the Brazilian Workers’ Party Roberto Jefferson,
businessman Luciano Hang, and congresspersons Douglas Garcia, Gil
Diniz, Carla Zambelli, Bia Kicis, Junio Amaral, Filipe Barros, Luiz
Phillipe Orleans e Bragança, and Daniel Silveira.
One of these parliamentarians, Zambelli, said that “every person who
respects the law has the obligation to repudiate these searches within
the scope of an illegal and unconstitutional investigation.”
By the same token, another congresswoman, Kicis, stated: “We are
living in dark times of brazen attack on democracy. Don’t forget the
people who are celebrating the abuses of authority and undemocratic
acts by Justice Alexandre de Moraes against journalists, comedians,
businessmen and any other common people. They are accomplices of the
dictatorship. I have never been silent against tyranny or opponents.”
On Aug. 23, Moraes directed the federal police to execute search
warrants in five states targeting at least eight businessmen. He
ordered police to raid their homes, to access their bank accounts, and
suspend their social media accounts. These citizens are being
investigated over a couple of messages posted in their WhatsApp group
whereby some allegedly dared to say they would prefer another military
regime to the return of the far-left candidate Lula da Silva to the
presidency.
Epoch Times Photo Former president of Brazil Luiz Inacio Lula da Silva
speaks during an event to announce Lula’s pre-candidacy for October
presidential elections along with running mate Geraldo Alckmin at Expo
Center Norte in Sao Paulo, Brazil, on May 7, 2022. (Buda Mendes/Getty
Images)
Moraes also ordered their bank accounts blocked. One of those targeted
by the operation was Luciano Hang, the founder of retail chain Havan
and a Bolsonaro supporter with millions of followers on social media.
Although Hang says he has “never spoken of a coup” and he has “always
defended democracy and freedom of expression,” Moraes ordered the
blocking of all his social media accounts, including Twitter,
Instagram, Facebook, YouTube, WhatsApp, and TikTok.
“They can take away my social networks, but they’ll never shut me up!”
said Hang, who built a department store chain known for displaying
replicas of the Statute of Liberty out front. “Say no to censorship!
You could be next,” he posted on his Twitter account before it was
closed by the court order issued by Moraes.
Other businessmen who reportedly had their social media and bank
accounts blocked include Meyer Joseph Nigri, chairman and former CEO
of property developer Tecnisa, Jose Isaac Peres, founder of shopping
mall company Multiplan, and Afranio Barreira Filho, owner of the
restaurant chain Coco Bambu.
Brazil’s Democracy Under Threat
Bolsonaro says democracy is now under serious attack in the country.
He has accused these unelected judges of practising political
interference and trying to deploy a judicial dictatorship.
“Brazil is on the road to dictatorship. This is how dictatorships
start now. You lose your freedom little by little, then one day you
look, and you are completely tied up,” he told network Jovem Pan.
After knowing all these extraordinary things, who would disagree? The
democratic system is clearly being undermined by the replacement of
the rule of law with the rule of judges. In fact, the premise that
unelected judges know better what is best for the nation is elitist
and utterly undemocratic.
It is ironic to see that now the major threat to democracy in Brazil
now comes not from elected politicians but from a highly anachronistic
judicial oligarchy.
1
0
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Anarcho-capitalism
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Talk:Anarcho-capitalism/Archive_1
...
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Talk:Anarcho-capitalism/Archive_28
Anarcho-capitalism
>From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
A two-colored flag, split diagonally, with yellow at the top and black
at the bottom
The black and gold flag, a symbol of anarchism (black) and capitalism
(gold) which according to Murray Rothbard was first flown in 1963 in
Colorado[1] and is also used by the Swedish AnarkoKapitalistisk
Front[2]
Part of a series on
Anarcho-capitalism
Flag of Anarcho-capitalism.svg
Origins
Age of Enlightenment
Aristotelianism
Austrian School
Marginalism
School of Salamanca
Subjective theory of value
Classical liberalism
French Liberal School
Homestead principle
Labor theory of property
Laissez-faire
Physiocracy
Individualist anarchism
Market anarchism
Concepts
Anti-statism
Civil rights
Counter-economics
Decentralization
Deregulation
Economic liberalism
Free market
Free-market anarchism
Free-market roads
Free trade
Freedom of contract
Individualism
Jurisdictional arbitrage
Laissez-faire
Land ownership
Natural Law
Non-aggression principle
Polycentric law
Private defense agency
Private governance
Private military company
Private police
Private property
Privatization
Propertarianism
Property rights
Right to own property
Self-ownership
Spontaneous order
Taxation as theft
Title-transfer theory of contract
Voluntaryism
People
Bruce L. Benson
Walter Block
Bryan Caplan
Gerard Casey
Anthony de Jasay
David D. Friedman
Hans-Hermann Hoppe
Michael Huemer
Stephan Kinsella
Michael Malice
Stefan Molyneux
Wendy McElroy
Lew Rockwell
Murray Rothbard
Joseph Salerno
Jeffrey Tucker
Thomas Woods
Works
Defending the Undefendable
Democracy: The God That Failed
The Ethics of Liberty
For a New Liberty
The Machinery of Freedom
The Market for Liberty
The Problem of Political Authority
To Serve and Protect
The Voluntary City
Issues
Abortion
Anarchism
Capital punishment
Criticism
Foreign affairs
Immigration
Inheritance
Intellectual property
Internal debates
LGBT rights
Minarchism
Objectivism
Political parties
Politics
Theories of law
Related topics
Agorism
Right-libertarianism
Libertarianism in the United States
Left-libertarianism
icon Capitalism portal
icon Politics portal
v
t
e
Part of a series on
Capitalism
Concepts
Business
Business cycle
Businessperson
Capital
Capital accumulation
Capital markets
Company
Corporation
Competitive markets
Economic interventionism
Economic liberalism
Economic surplus
Entrepreneurship
Fictitious capital
Financial market
Free price system
Free market
Goods and services
Investor
Invisible hand
Visible hand
Liberalization
Marginalism
Money
Private property
Privatization
Profit
Rent seeking
Supply and demand
Surplus value
Value
Wage labour
Economic systems
Anglo-Saxon
Authoritarian
Corporate
Dirigist
Free-market
Humanistic
Laissez-faire
Liberal
Libertarian
Market
Mercantilist
Mixed
Monopoly
State
National
Neoliberal
Nordic
Private
Raw
Regulated market
Regulatory
Rhine
Social
State
State-sponsored
Welfare
Economic theories
American
Austrian
Chartalism
MMT
Chicago
Classical
Institutional
Keynesian
Neo-
New
Post-
Critique of political economy
Critique of work
Marxist
Monetarist
Neoclassical
New institutional
Supply-side
Origins
Age of Enlightenment
Capitalism and Islam
Commercial Revolution
Feudalism
Industrial Revolution
Mercantilism
Primitive accumulation
Physiocracy
Simple commodity production
Development
Advanced
Consumer
Community
Corporate
Crony
Finance
Global
Illiberal
Late
Marxist
Merchant
Progressive
Rentier
State monopoly
Technological
People
Adam Smith
John Stuart Mill
David Ricardo
Thomas Robert Malthus
Jean-Baptiste Say
Karl Marx
Milton Friedman
Friedrich Hayek
John Maynard Keynes
Alfred Marshall
Vilfredo Pareto
Leon Walras
Ludwig von Mises
Ayn Rand
Murray Rothbard
Joseph Schumpeter
Thorstein Veblen
Max Weber
Ronald Coase
Related topics and criticism
Anti-capitalism
Capitalist state
Consumerism
Crisis theory
Criticism of capitalism
Critique of political economy
Critique of work
Cronyism
Culture of capitalism
Evergreening
Exploitation of labour
Globalization
History
History of theory
Market economy
Periodizations of capitalism
Perspectives on capitalism
Post-capitalism
Speculation
Spontaneous order
Venture philanthropy
Wage slavery
Ideologies
Anarcho
Authoritarian
Classical liberalism
Democratic
Dirigisme
Eco
Humanistic
Inclusive
Liberal
Liberalism
Libertarian
Neo
Neoliberalism
Objectivism
Ordoliberalism
Privatism
Right-libertarianism
Third Way
icon Capitalism portal
icon Business portal
v
t
e
Part of a series on
Libertarianism
in the United States
Origins
Abolitionism in the United States
Age of Enlightenment
Anti-Federalism
Classical liberalism
Individualist anarchism in the United States
Transcendentalism
Concepts
Anti-imperialism
Civil libertarianism
Counter-economics
Decentralization
Departurism
Economic freedom
Evictionism
Free market
Free-market environmentalism
Free migration
Free trade
Free will
Freedom of association
Freedom of contract
Freedom of speech
Homestead principle
Individuality
Individualism
Libertarianism
Liberty
Limited government
Localism
Marriage privatization
Natural rights and legal rights
Non-aggression principle
Non-interventionism
Non-politics
Non-voting
Polycentric law
Private defense agency
Private property
Public choice theory
Restorative justice
Right to bear arms
Rugged Individualism
Self-ownership
Single tax
Small government
Spontaneous order
Stateless society
Tax resistance
Title-transfer theory of contract
Voluntary association
Voluntary society
Schools
Austro-libertarianism
Bleeding-heart libertarianism
Christian libertarianism
Consequentialist libertarianism
Geolibertarianism
Green libertarianism
Natural-rights libertarianism
Neo-libertarianism
Paleolibertarianism
Technolibertarianism
Theory
Agorism
Anarcho-capitalism
Autarchism
Constitutionalism
Fusionism
Libertarian feminism
Left-wing market anarchism
Libertarian conservatism
Libertarian paternalism
Libertarian socialism
Libertarian transhumanism
Minarchism
Panarchism
Propertarianism
Voluntaryism
Economics
Austrian School
Economic liberalism
Fiscal conservatism
Georgism
Laissez-faire
Neoliberalism
Supply-side economics
People
Amash
Andrews
Barnett
Block
Brennan
Burt
Chamberlain
Caplan
Carson
Chartier
Chodorov
Chomsky
Cleveland
Coolidge
Epstein
D. Friedman
M. Friedman
P. Friedman
R. Friedman
Galambos
Garrett
George
Gillespie
Goldwater
Greene
Harper
Hazlitt
Heinlein
Hess
Heywood
Hoppe
Hospers
Huemer
Jillette
Johnson
Jorgensen
Kinsella
C. Koch
D. Koch
Konkin III
C. Lane
R. Lane
LeFevre
Machan
McElroy
Mencken
Mises
Napolitano
Nock
Nolan
Nozick
Paterson
Paul
Postrel
Pugsley
Rand
Read
Rockwell
Rothbard
Sarwark
Schulman
Sciabarra
Scott
Smith
Sowell
Skousen
Spooner
Stossel
Swartz
Szasz
Taleb
Teller
Thiel
Thoreau
Tucker
Ventura
Warren
Wilder
Williams
Wilson
Woods
History
New Left
Old Right
Issues
Abortion
Capital punishment
Criticism
Foreign affairs
Immigration
Intellectual property
Internal debates
LGBT rights
Objectivism
Political parties
Politics
State
Theories of law
Culture
Come and take it
Gadsden flag
Libertarian science fiction
Ron Swanson
Organizations
Cato Institute
Free State Project
Foundation for Economic Education
International Alliance of Libertarian Parties
Libertarian Party
Liberty International
Mises Institute
Reason Foundation
Students for a Democratic Society
Students for Liberty
Works
The Anarchist Cookbook
Anarchy, State, and Utopia
The Betrayal of the American Right
Civil Disobedience
Conceived in Liberty
Defending the Undefendable
The Discovery of Freedom
End the Fed
The Ethics of Liberty
For a New Liberty
Free to Choose
The God of the Machine
Liberty
The Machinery of Freedom
Man, Economy and State
The Moon is a Harsh Mistress
The Mainspring of Human Progress
The Market for Liberty
No, They Can't
No Treason
New Libertarian Manifesto
Our Enemy, the State
The Problem of Political Authority
Progress and Poverty
Protection or Free Trade
Radicals for Capitalism
Seeing Like a State
To Serve and Protect
The Unconstitutionality of Slavery
Related topics
American militia movement
Boogaloo movement
Conservatism in the United States
Dark Enlightenment
Left-libertarianism
Liberalism in the United States
Libertarian Democrat
Libertarian Republican
Libertarianism in Hong Kong
Libertarianism in South Africa
Libertarianism in the United Kingdom
New Right
Objectivism
On Democracy in America
Outline of libertarianism
Right-libertarianism
Sovereign citizen movement
icon Liberalism portal
Conservatism portal
coin Libertarianism portal
v
t
e
Part of a series on
Individualism
Topics and concepts
Autonomy
Civil liberties
Do it yourself
Eremitism
Free love
Freethought
Human rights
Individual
Individual rights
Individual reclamation
Individuation
Laissez-faire
Libertine
Liberty
Methodological individualism
Negative liberty
Personal property
Positive liberty
Private property
Self-actualization
Self-ownership
Self-sufficiency
Subjectivity
Thinkers
Antiphon
Aristippus
Aristotle
Armand
Camus
Diogenes
Emerson
Epicurus
Godwin
Goldman
Hayek
Hess
Igualada
Jefferson
Laozi
Libertad
Locke
Jung
Hipparchia
Mencken
Mill
Mises
Montaigne
Nietzsche
Novatore
Nozick
Onfray
Palante
Quelle
Rand
Rothbard
Ryner
Sade
Schopenhauer
Smith
Spencer
Spooner
Stirner
Thoreau
Tucker
Walker
Warren
Wilde
Zeno
Yang
Philosophies
Autarchism
Anarchism
Individualist anarchism
Anarcho-capitalism
Egoist anarchism
Left-wing market anarchism
Social anarchism
Egoism
Ethical egoism
Rational egoism
Existentialism
Hedonism
Humanism
Individualist feminism
Equity feminism
Liberal feminism
Liberalism
Classical liberalism
Libertarianism
Left-libertarianism
Libertarian socialism
Right-libertarianism
Minarchism
Mutualism
Objectivism
Subjectivism
Voluntaryism
Principal concerns
Anti-individualism
Authoritarianism
Collectivism
Conformity
Dogmatism
Group rights
Herd mentality
Indoctrination
Mass society
Mobbing
Social engineering
Statism
Tyranny
Tyranny of the majority
Theocracy
Totalitarianism
v
t
e
Anarcho-capitalism (or, colloquially, ancap)[3][4] is an
anti-statist[5] libertarian[6] political philosophy and economic
theory that seeks to abolish centralized states in favor of stateless
societies with systems of private property enforced by private
agencies, the non-aggression principle, free markets and the
right-libertarian interpretation of self-ownership, which extends the
concept to include control of private property as part of the self. In
the absence of statute, anarcho-capitalists hold that society tends to
contractually self-regulate and civilize through participation in the
free market which they describe as a voluntary society.[7][8][9] In a
theoretical anarcho-capitalist society, the system of private property
would still exist and be enforced by private defense agencies and/or
insurance companies selected by customers which would operate
competitively in a market and fulfill the roles of courts and the
police.[9][10][11]
According to its proponents, various historical theorists have
espoused philosophies similar to anarcho-capitalism,[12] but the first
person to use the term anarcho-capitalism was Murray Rothbard, in the
1940s.[13] Rothbard synthesized elements from the Austrian School,
classical liberalism and 19th-century American individualist
anarchists and mutualists Lysander Spooner and Benjamin Tucker while
rejecting their labor theory of value and the anti-capitalist and
socialist norms they derived from it.[14][15][16] Rothbard's
anarcho-capitalist society would operate under a mutually agreed-upon
"legal code which would be generally accepted, and which the courts
would pledge themselves to follow".[17] This legal code would
recognize contracts, private property, self-ownership and tort law in
keeping with the non-aggression principle.[17][18]
Anarcho-capitalists and right-libertarians cite several historical
precedents of what they believe to be examples of
anarcho-capitalism,[24] including Anglo‐Saxon England,[5][7] the Free
cities of medieval Europe, Medieval Iceland, the American Old West,
Gaelic Ireland, Somalia from 1991 to 2006, and law merchant, admiralty
law, and early common law.
Anarcho-capitalism is distinguished from both minarchism, which
advocates a night-watchman state limited to protecting individuals
from aggression and enforcing private property;[25] anarchism, an
anti-capitalist movement which holds that capitalism is incompatible
with social and economic equality; and social anarchism, a branch of
anarchism that sees individual freedom as interrelated with mutual
aid. Anarcho-capitalists reject the libertarian socialist economic
theories of anarchism, arguing that they are inherently authoritarian
or require authoritarianism to achieve, while believing that there is
no coercion under capitalism. Despite its name, anarcho-capitalism
lies outside the tradition of anarchism and is more closely affiliated
with capitalism, right-libertarianism, and
liberalism.[26][27][28][29][30] Traditional anarchist schools of
thought oppose and reject capitalism, and consider
'anarcho-capitalism' to be a contradiction in terms.[31][32][33]
Anarcho-capitalism is usually seen as part of the New Right.[29][34]
Contents
1 Philosophy
1.1 On the state
1.2 Non-aggression principle
1.3 Property
1.3.1 Private property
1.3.2 Common property
1.3.3 Intellectual property
1.4 Contractual society
1.5 Law and order and the use of violence
1.6 Free-market in children
2 Influences
2.1 Anarchism
2.2 Classical liberalism
2.3 Individualist anarchism
3 Historical precedents
3.1 Free cities of medieval Europe
3.2 Medieval Iceland
3.3 American Old West
3.4 Gaelic Ireland
3.5 Law merchant, admiralty law, and early common law
3.6 Somalia from 1991 to 2006
4 Criticism
4.1 State, justice and defense
4.2 Rights and freedom
4.3 Economics and property
5 Literature
6 See also
7 References
8 Further reading
9 External links
Philosophy
Murray Rothbard wearing glasses, a suit and a bow-tie and sat on an
armchair, looking rightwards
Murray Rothbard (1926–1995), who coined the word anarcho-capitalism
This section has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss
these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove these
template messages)
This section may be confusing or unclear to readers. (July 2019)
This section relies too much on references to primary sources. (July 2020)
Author J Michael Oliver says that during the 1960s, a philosophical
movement arose in the United States that championed "reason, ethical
egoism, and free-market capitalism". According to Oliver,
anarcho-capitalism is a political theory which logically follows the
philosophical conclusions of Objectivism, a philosophical system
developed by Russian-American writer Ayn Rand.[35] Professor Lisa
Duggan also says that Rand's anti-statist, pro–"free market" stances
went on to shape the politics of anarcho-capitalism.[36]
According to Patrik Schumacher, the political ideology and programme
of Anarcho-capitalism envisages the radicalization of the neoliberal
"rollback of the state", and calls for the extension of
"entrepreneurial freedom" and "competitive market rationality" to the
point where the scope for private enterprise is all-encompassing and
"leaves no space for state action whatsoever".[37]
On the state
Anarcho-capitalists opposition to the state is reflected in their goal
of keeping but privatizing all functions of the state.[37][38][39]
They see capitalism and the "free market" as the basis for a free and
prosperous society. Murray Rothbard, who is credited with coining the
term anarcho-capitalism,[40][41] stated that the difference between
free-market capitalism and state capitalism is the difference between
"peaceful, voluntary exchange" and a "collusive partnership" between
business and government that "uses coercion to subvert the free
market".[42]
Rothbard argued that all government services, including defense, are
inefficient because they lack a market-based pricing mechanism
regulated by "the voluntary decisions of consumers purchasing services
that fulfill their highest-priority needs" and by investors seeking
the most profitable enterprises to invest in.[43]: 1051 Furthermore,
Linda and Morris Tannehill believe that no coercive monopoly of force
can arise on a truly free market and that a government's citizenry can
not desert them in favor of a competent protection and defense
agency.[44]
Rothbard used the term anarcho-capitalism to distinguish his
philosophy from anarchism that opposes private property[45] as well as
to distinguish it from individualist anarchism.[46] Other terms
sometimes used by proponents of the philosophy include:
Individualist anarchism[47][48]
Natural order[12]
Ordered anarchy[12]
Private-law society[12]
Private-property anarchy[12]
Radical capitalism[12]
Maverick Edwards of the Liberty University describes
anarcho-capitalism as a political, social, and economic theory that
places markets as the central "governing body" and where government no
longer "grants" rights to its citizenry.[49]
Non-aggression principle
Main article: Non-aggression principle
Writer Stanisław Wójtowicz says that although anarcho-capitalists are
against centralized states, they hold that all people would naturally
share and agree to a specific moral theory based on the non-aggression
principle.[50] While the Friedmanian formulation of anarcho-capitalism
is robust to the presence of violence and in fact, assumes some degree
of violence will occur,[51] anarcho-capitalism as formulated by
Rothbard and others holds strongly to the central libertarian
nonaggression axiom,[50] sometimes non-aggression principle. Rothbard
wrote:
The basic axiom of libertarian political theory holds that every
man is a self-owner, having absolute jurisdiction over his own body.
In effect, this means that no one else may justly invade, or aggress
against, another's person. It follows then that each person justly
owns whatever previously unowned resources he appropriates or "mixes
his labor with". From these twin axioms – self-ownership and
"homesteading" – stem the justification for the entire system of
property rights titles in a free-market society. This system
establishes the right of every man to his own person, the right of
donation, of bequest (and, concomitantly, the right to receive the
bequest or inheritance), and the right of contractual exchange of
property titles.[18]
Rothbard's defense of the self-ownership principle stems from what he
believed to be his falsification of all other alternatives, namely
that either a group of people can own another group of people, or that
no single person has full ownership over one's self. Rothbard
dismisses these two cases on the basis that they cannot result in a
universal ethic, i.e. a just natural law that can govern all people,
independent of place and time. The only alternative that remains to
Rothbard is self-ownership which he believes is both axiomatic and
universal.[52]
In general, the non-aggression axiom is described by Rothbard as a
prohibition against the initiation of force, or the threat of force,
against persons (in which he includes direct violence, assault and
murder) or property (in which he includes fraud, burglary, theft and
taxation).[19]: 24–25 The initiation of force is usually referred to
as aggression or coercion. The difference between anarcho-capitalists
and other libertarians is largely one of the degree to which they take
this axiom. Minarchist libertarians such as libertarian political
parties would retain the state in some smaller and less invasive form,
retaining at the very least public police, courts, and military.
However, others might give further allowance for other government
programs. In contrast, Rothbard rejects any level of "state
intervention", defining the state as a coercive monopoly and as the
only entity in human society, excluding acknowledged criminals, that
derives its income entirely from coercion, in the form of taxation,
which Rothbard describes as "compulsory seizure of the property of the
State's inhabitants, or subjects."[52]
Some anarcho-capitalists such as Rothbard accept the non-aggression
axiom on an intrinsic moral or natural law basis. It is in terms of
the non-aggression principle that Rothbard defined his interpretation
of anarchism, "a system which provides no legal sanction for such
aggression ['against person and property']"; and wrote that "what
anarchism proposes to do, then, is to abolish the State, i.e. to
abolish the regularized institution of aggressive coercion".[53] In an
interview published in the American libertarian journal The New
Banner, Rothbard stated that "capitalism is the fullest expression of
anarchism, and anarchism is the fullest expression of capitalism".[54]
Property
Private property
Anarcho-capitalists postulate the privatization of everything,
including cities with all their infrastructures, public spaces,
streets and urban management systems.[37][55]
Central to Rothbardian anarcho-capitalism are the concepts of
self-ownership and original appropriation that combines personal and
private property. Hans-Hermann Hoppe wrote:
Everyone is the proper owner of his own physical body as well as
of all places and nature-given goods that he occupies and puts to use
by means of his body, provided only that no one else has already
occupied or used the same places and goods before him. This ownership
of "originally appropriated" places and goods by a person implies his
right to use and transform these places and goods in any way he sees
fit, provided only that he does not change thereby uninvitedly the
physical integrity of places and goods originally appropriated by
another person. In particular, once a place or good has been first
appropriated by, in John Locke's phrase, 'mixing one's labor' with it,
ownership in such places and goods can be acquired only by means of a
voluntary – contractual – transfer of its property title from a
previous to a later owner.[56]
Rothbard however rejected the Lockean proviso, and followed the rule
of "first come, first served", without any consideration of how much
resources are left for other individuals, which opposed John Locke's
beliefs.[57][58]
Anarcho-capitalists advocate private ownership of the means of
production and the allocation of the product of labor created by
workers within the context of wage labour and the free market – that
is through decisions made by property and capital owners, regardless
of what an individual needs or does not need.[59] Original
appropriation allows an individual to claim any never-before-used
resources, including land and by improving or otherwise using it, own
it with the same "absolute right" as their own body, and retaining
those rights forever, regardless of whether the resource is still
being used by them. According to Rothbard, property can only come
about through labor, therefore original appropriation of land is not
legitimate by merely claiming it or building a fence around it—it is
only by using land and by mixing one's labor with it that original
appropriation is legitimized: "Any attempt to claim a new resource
that someone does not use would have to be considered invasive of the
property right of whoever the first user will turn out to be".
Rothbard argued that the resource need not continue to be used in
order for it to be the person's property as "for once his labor is
mixed with the natural resource, it remains his owned land. His labor
has been irretrievably mixed with the land, and the land is therefore
his or his assigns' in perpetuity".[60]: 170
Rothbard also spoke about a theory of justice in property rights:
It is not enough to call simply for the defense of "the rights of
private property"; there must be an adequate theory of justice in
property rights, else any property that some State once decreed to be
"private" must now be defended by libertarians, no matter how unjust
the procedure or how mischievous its consequences.[46]
In Justice and Property Right, Rothbard wrote that "any identifiable
owner (the original victim of theft or his heir) must be accorded his
property".[61][62] In the case of slavery, Rothbard claimed that in
many cases "the old plantations and the heirs and descendants of the
former slaves can be identified, and the reparations can become highly
specific indeed". Rothbard believed slaves rightfully own any land
they were forced to work on under the homestead principle. If property
is held by the state, Rothbard advocated its confiscation and "return
to the private sector",[63] writing that "any property in the hands of
the State is in the hands of thieves, and should be liberated as
quickly as possible".[64] Rothbard proposed that state universities be
seized by the students and faculty under the homestead principle.
Rothbard also supported the expropriation of nominally "private
property" if it is the result of state-initiated force such as
businesses that receive grants and subsidies.[65] Rothbard further
proposed that businesses who receive at least 50% of their funding
from the state be confiscated by the workers,[66][67] writing: "What
we libertarians object to, then, is not government per se but crime,
what we object to is unjust or criminal property titles; what we are
for is not 'private' property per se but just, innocent, non-criminal
private property".[64]
Similarly, Karl Hess wrote that "libertarianism wants to advance
principles of property but that it in no way wishes to defend, willy
nilly, all property which now is called private ... Much of that
property is stolen. Much is of dubious title. All of it is deeply
intertwined with an immoral, coercive state system".[68]
By accepting an axiomatic definition of private property and property
rights, anarcho-capitalists deny the legitimacy of a state on
principle.[original research?] Hans-Hermann Hoppe argues:
For, apart from ruling out as unjustified all activities such as
murder, homicide, rape, trespass, robbery, burglary, theft, and fraud,
the ethics of private property is also incompatible with the existence
of a state defined as an agency that possesses a compulsory
territorial monopoly of ultimate decision-making (jurisdiction) and/or
the right to tax.[56]
Anarchists view capitalism as an inherently authoritarian and
hierarchical system and seek the abolishment of private property.[69]
There is disagreement between anarchists and anarcho-capitalists[70]
as the former generally rejects anarcho-capitalism as a form of
anarchism and considers anarcho-capitalism a contradiction in
terms,[71][72][73] while the latter holds that the abolishment of
private property would require expropriation which is
"counterproductive to order" and would require a state.[74]
Common property
As opposed to anarchists,[75] most anarcho-capitalists reject the
commons.[76] However, some of them propose that non-state public or
community property can also exist in an anarcho-capitalist
society.[76] For anarcho-capitalists, what is important is that it is
"acquired" and transferred without help or hindrance from what they
call the "compulsory state". Deontological anarcho-capitalists believe
that the only just and most economically beneficial way to acquire
property is through voluntary trade, gift, or labor-based original
appropriation, rather than through aggression or fraud.[77]
Anarcho-capitalists state that there could be cases where common
property may develop in a Lockean natural rights framework.
Anarcho-capitalists make the example of a number of private businesses
which may arise in an area, each owning the land and buildings that
they use, but they argue that the paths between them become cleared
and trodden incrementally through customer and commercial movement.
These thoroughfares may become valuable to the community, but
according to them ownership cannot be attributed to any single person
and original appropriation does not apply because many contributed the
labor necessary to create them. In order to prevent it from falling to
the "tragedy of the commons", anarcho-capitalists suggest
transitioning from common to private property, wherein an individual
would make a homesteading claim based on disuse, acquire title by the
assent of the community consensus, form a corporation with other
involved parties, or other means.[76]
Randall G. Holcombe see challenges stemming from the idea of common
property under anarcho-capitalism, such as whether an individual might
claim fishing rights in the area of a major shipping lane and thereby
forbid passage through it.[76] In contrast, Hoppe's work on
anarcho-capitalist theory is based on the assumption that all property
is privately held, "including all streets, rivers, airports, and
harbors" which forms the foundation of his views on immigration.[76]
Intellectual property
Main article: Intellectual property
Some anarcho-capitalists strongly oppose intellectual property (i.e.,
trademarks, patents, copyrights). Stephan N. Kinsella argues that
ownership only relates to tangible assets.[78]
Contractual society
The society envisioned by anarcho-capitalists has been labelled by
them as a "contractual society" which Rothbard described as "a society
based purely on voluntary action, entirely unhampered by violence or
threats of violence"[60]: 84 The system relies on contracts between
individuals as the legal framework which would be enforced by private
police and security forces as well as private
arbitrations.[79][80][81]
Rothbard argues that limited liability for corporations could also
exist through contract, arguing that "[c]orporations are not at all
monopolistic privileges; they are free associations of individuals
pooling their capital. On the purely free market, those men would
simply announce to their creditors that their liability is limited to
the capital specifically invested in the corporation".[43]: 1144
However, corporations created in this way would not be able to
replicate the limit on liabilities arising non-contractually such as
liability in tort for environmental disasters or personal injury which
corporations currently enjoy. Rothbard acknowledges that "limited
liability for torts is the illegitimate conferring of a special
privilege".[43]: 1144
There are limits to the right to contract under some interpretations
of anarcho-capitalism. Rothbard believes that the right to contract is
based in inalienable rights[52] and because of this any contract that
implicitly violates those rights can be voided at will, preventing a
person from permanently selling himself or herself into unindentured
slavery. However, Rothbard justifies the practice of child
selling.[82][83] Other interpretations conclude that banning such
contracts would in itself be an unacceptably invasive interference in
the right to contract.[84]
Included in the right of contract is "the right to contract oneself
out for employment by others". While anarchists criticize wage labour
describing it as wage slavery, anarcho-capitalists view it as a
consensual contract.[85][citation needed] Some anarcho-capitalists
prefer to see self-employment prevail over wage labor. David D.
Friedman has expressed a preference for a society where "almost
everyone is self-employed" and "instead of corporations there are
large groups of entrepreneurs related by trade, not authority. Each
sells not his time, but what his time produces".[85]
Law and order and the use of violence
Different anarcho-capitalists propose different forms of
anarcho-capitalism and one area of disagreement is in the area of law.
In The Market for Liberty, Morris and Linda Tannehill object to any
statutory law whatsoever. They argue that all one has to do is ask if
one is aggressing against another in order to decide if an act is
right or wrong.[86] However, while also supporting a "natural
prohibition"[clarification needed] on force and fraud, Rothbard
supports the establishment of a mutually agreed-upon centralized
libertarian legal code which private courts would pledge to follow, as
he presumes a high degree of convergence amongst individuals about
what constitutes natural justice.[87]
Unlike both the Tannehills and Rothbard who see an ideological
commonality of ethics and morality as a requirement, David D. Friedman
proposes that "the systems of law will be produced for profit on the
open market, just as books and bras are produced today. There could be
competition among different brands of law, just as there is
competition among different brands of cars".[88] Friedman says whether
this would lead to a libertarian society "remains to be proven". He
says it is a possibility that very un-libertarian laws may result,
such as laws against drugs, but he thinks this would be rare. He
reasons that "if the value of a law to its supporters is less than its
cost to its victims, that law ... will not survive in an
anarcho-capitalist society".[89]
Anarcho-capitalists only accept the collective defense of individual
liberty (i.e. courts, military, or police forces) insofar as such
groups are formed and paid for on an explicitly voluntary basis.
However, their complaint is not just that the state's defensive
services are funded by taxation, but that the state assumes it is the
only legitimate practitioner of physical force—that is, they believe
it forcibly prevents the private sector from providing comprehensive
security, such as a police, judicial and prison systems to protect
individuals from aggressors. Anarcho-capitalists believe that there is
nothing morally superior about the state which would grant it, but not
private individuals, a right to use physical force to restrain
aggressors. If competition in security provision were allowed to
exist, prices would also be lower and services would be better
according to anarcho-capitalists. According to Molinari: "Under a
regime of liberty, the natural organization of the security industry
would not be different from that of other industries".[90] Proponents
believe that private systems of justice and defense already exist,
naturally forming where the market is allowed to "compensate for the
failure of the state",[citation needed] namely private arbitration,
security guards, neighborhood watch groups and so on.[91][92][93][94]
These private courts and police are sometimes referred to generically
as private defense agencies (PDAs). The defense of those unable to pay
for such protection might be financed by charitable organizations
relying on voluntary donation rather than by state institutions
relying on taxation, or by cooperative self-help by groups of
individuals.[19]: 223 Edward Stringham argues that private
adjudication of disputes could enable the market to internalize
externalities and provide services that customers desire.[95][96]
The death of general Joseph Warren at the Battle of Bunker Hill during
the American Revolutionary War, a war which anarcho-capitalists such
as Murray Rothbard admired and believed it was the only American war
that could be justified[citation needed]
In the context of revolution, Rothbard stated that the American
Revolutionary War was the only war involving the United States that
could be justified.[97] Some anarcho-capitalists such as Rothbard feel
that violent revolution is counter-productive and prefer voluntary
forms of economic secession to the extent possible.[98] Retributive
justice is often a component of the contracts imagined for an
anarcho-capitalist society. According to Matthew O'Keefee, some
anarcho-capitalists believe prisons or indentured servitude would be
justifiable institutions to deal with those who violate
anarcho-capitalist property relations while others believe exile or
forced restitution are sufficient.[99]
Bruce L. Benson argues that legal codes may impose punitive damages
for intentional torts in the interest of deterring crime. Benson gives
the example of a thief who breaks into a house by picking a lock. Even
if caught before taking anything, Benson argues that the thief would
still owe the victim for violating the sanctity of his property
rights. Benson opines that despite the lack of objectively measurable
losses in such cases, "standardized rules that are generally perceived
to be fair by members of the community would, in all likelihood, be
established through precedent, allowing judgments to specify payments
that are reasonably appropriate for most criminal offenses".[100]
Morris and Linda Tannehill raise a similar example, saying that a bank
robber who had an attack of conscience and returned the money would
still owe reparations for endangering the employees' and customers'
lives and safety, in addition to the costs of the defense agency
answering the teller's call for help. However, they believe that the
robber's loss of reputation would be even more damaging. They suggest
that specialized companies would list aggressors so that anyone
wishing to do business with a man could first check his record,
provided they trust the veracity of the companies' records. They
further theorise that the bank robber would find insurance companies
listing him as a very poor risk and other firms would be reluctant to
enter into contracts with him.[101]
Free-market in children
4 Children for Sale, Chicago (1948).
Main article: Child selling
Anarcho-capitalism as proposed by Murray Rothbard advocates the
ownership of children and their sale. According to Rothbard: "the
purely free society will have a flourishing free market in children.
Superficially, this sounds monstrous and inhuman. But closer thought
will reveal the superior humanism of such a market."[102] Walter Block
also supports the sale of children, stating that adoptive parents not
being able to pay biological parents "is responsible for the trauma
and heartbreak which attend adoption in the United States today".[103]
Influences
Murray Rothbard has listed different ideologies of which his
interpretations, he said, have influenced anarcho-capitalism.[14][15]
This includes his interpretation of anarchism, and more precisely
individualist anarchism; classical liberalism and the Austrian School
of economic thought. Scholars additionally associate
anarcho-capitalism with neo-classical liberalism, radical
neoliberalism and right-libertarianism.[26][30][104]
Anarchism
Main article: Anarchism and capitalism
In both its social and individualist forms, anarchism is usually
considered an anti-capitalist[105][106] and radical left-wing or
far-left[107][108][109] movement that promotes libertarian socialist
economic theories such as collectivism, communism, individualism,
mutualism and syndicalism.[110] Because anarchism is usually described
alongside libertarian Marxism as the libertarian wing of the socialist
movement and as having a historical association with anti-capitalism
and socialism, anarchists believe that capitalism is incompatible with
social and economic equality and therefore do not recognize
anarcho-capitalism as an anarchist school of thought.[26][104][30] In
particular, anarchists argue that capitalist transactions are not
voluntary and that maintaining the class structure of a capitalist
society requires coercion which is incompatible with an anarchist
society.[111][112] The usage of libertarian is also in dispute.[113]
While both anarchists and anarcho-capitalists have used it,
libertarian was synonymous with anarchist until the mid-20th century,
when anarcho-capitalist theory developed.[104][114]
Anarcho-capitalists are distinguished from the dominant anarchist
tradition by their relation to property and capital. While both
anarchism and anarcho-capitalism share general antipathy towards power
by government authority, the latter exempts power wielded through
free-market capitalism. Anarchists, including egoists such as Max
Stirner, have supported the protection of an individual's freedom from
powers of both government and private property owners.[115] In
contrast, while condemning governmental encroachment on personal
liberties, anarcho-capitalists support freedoms based on private
property rights. Anarcho-capitalist theorist Murray Rothbard argued
that protesters should rent a street for protest from its owners. The
abolition of public amenities is a common theme in some
anarcho-capitalist writings.[116]
As anarcho-capitalism puts laissez-faire economics before economic
equality, it is commonly viewed as incompatible with the
anti-capitalist and egalitarian tradition of anarchism. Although
anarcho-capitalist theory implies the abolition of the state in favour
of a fully laissez-faire economy,[117] it lies outside the tradition
of anarchism.[119] While using the language of anarchism,[120]
anarcho-capitalism only shares anarchism's antipathy towards the
state[117] and not anarchism's antipathy towards hierarchy as
theorists expect from anarcho-capitalist economic power
relations.[120] It follows a different paradigm from anarchism and has
a fundamentally different approach and goals.[120] In spite of the
anarcho- in its title,[120] anarcho-capitalism is more closely
affiliated with capitalism and right-libertarianism than with
anarchism.[121] Some within this laissez-faire tradition reject the
designation of anarcho-capitalism, believing that capitalism may
either refer to the laissez-faire market they support or the
government-regulated system that they oppose.[122]
Rothbard claimed that anarcho-capitalism is the only true form of
anarchism—the only form of anarchism that could possibly exist in
reality as he maintained that any other form presupposes authoritarian
enforcement of political ideology such as "redistribution of private
property" which he attributed to anarchism.[123] According to this
argument, the capitalist free market is "the natural situation" that
would result from people being free from state authority and entails
the establishment of all voluntary associations in society such as
cooperatives, non-profit organizations, businesses and so on.
Moreover, anarcho-capitalists, as well as classical liberal
minarchists, argue that the application of anarchist ideals as
advocated by what they term "left-wing anarchists" would require an
authoritarian body of some sort to impose it. Based on their
understanding and interpretation of anarchism, in order to forcefully
prevent people from accumulating capital, which they believe is a goal
of anarchists, there would necessarily be a redistributive
organization of some sort which would have the authority to in essence
exact a tax and re-allocate the resulting resources to a larger group
of people. They conclude that this theoretical body would inherently
have political power and would be nothing short of a state. The
difference between such an arrangement and an anarcho-capitalist
system is what anarcho-capitalists see as the voluntary nature of
organization within anarcho-capitalism contrasted with a "centralized
ideology" and a "paired enforcement mechanism" which they believe
would be necessary under what they describe as a "coercively"
egalitarian-anarchist system.[111]
Traditional anarchists reject the notion of capitalism, hierarchies
and private property.[124][125][31] Albert Meltzer argued that
anarcho-capitalism simply cannot be anarchism because capitalism and
the state are inextricably interlinked and because capitalism exhibits
domineering hierarchical structures such as that between an employer
and an employee.[126] Anna Morgenstern approaches this topic from the
opposite perspective, arguing that anarcho-capitalists are not really
capitalists because "mass concentration of capital is impossible"
without the state.[127] According to Jeremy Jennings, "[i]t is hard
not to conclude that these ideas", referring to anarcho-capitalism,
argued to have "roots deep in classical liberalism" more so than in
anarchism, "are described as anarchist only on the basis of a
misunderstanding of what anarchism is". For Jennings, "anarchism does
not stand for the untrammelled freedom of the individual (as the
'anarcho-capitalists' appear to believe) but, as we have already seen,
for the extension of individuality and community".[128] Similarly,
Barbara Goodwin, Emeritus Professor of Politics at the University of
East Anglia, Norwich, argues that anarcho-capitalism's "true place is
in the group of right-wing libertarians", not in anarchism.[129]
Nonetheless, some right-libertarian scholars like Michael Huemer, who
identify with the ideology, describe anarcho-capitalism as a "variety
of anarchism".[130] British author Andrew Heywood also believes that
"individualist anarchism overlaps with libertarianism and is usually
linked to a strong belief in the market as a self-regulating
mechanism, most obviously manifest in the form of
anarcho-capitalism".[131] Frank H. Brooks, author of The Individualist
Anarchists: An Anthology of Liberty (1881–1908), believes that
"anarchism has always included a significant strain of radical
individualism, from the hyperrationalism of Godwin, to the egoism of
Stirner, to the libertarians and anarcho-capitalists of today".[109]
While both anarchism and anarcho-capitalism are in opposition to the
state, it is a necessary but not sufficient condition because
anarchists and anarcho-capitalists interpret state-rejection
differently.[132][133][134][135] Austrian school economist David
Prychitko, in the context of anarcho-capitalism says that "while
society without a state is necessary for full-fledged anarchy, it is
nevertheless insufficient".[135] According to Ruth Kinna,
anarcho-capitalists are anti-statists who draw more on right-wing
liberal theory and the Austrian School than anarchist traditions.
Kinna writes that "[i]n order to highlight the clear distinction
between the two positions", anarchists describe anarcho-capitalists as
"propertarians".[38] Anarcho-capitalism is usually seen as part of the
New Right.[29][34]
Classical liberalism
Main article: Classical liberalism
Historian and libertarian Ralph Raico argued that what liberal
philosophers "had come up with was a form of individualist anarchism,
or, as it would be called today, anarcho-capitalism or market
anarchism".[136] He also said that Gustave de Molinari was proposing a
doctrine of the private production of security, a position which was
later taken up by Murray Rothbard.[136] Some anarcho-capitalists
consider Molinari to be the first proponent of
anarcho-capitalism.[137] In the preface to the 1977 English
translation by Murray Rothbard called The Production of Security the
"first presentation anywhere in human history of what is now called
anarcho-capitalism", although admitting that "Molinari did not use the
terminology, and probably would have balked at the name".[138]
Hans-Hermann Hoppe said that "the 1849 article 'The Production of
Security' is probably the single most important contribution to the
modern theory of anarcho-capitalism".[139] According to Hans-Hermann
Hoppe, one of the 19th century precursors of anarcho-capitalism were
philosopher Herbert Spencer, classical liberal Auberon Herbert and
liberal socialist Franz Oppenheimer.[12]
Ruth Kinna writes that anarcho-capitalism is a term coined by Murray
Rothbard to describe "a commitment to unregulated private property and
laissez-faire economics, prioritizing the liberty-rights of
individuals, unfettered by government regulation, to accumulate,
consume and determine the patterns of their lives as they see fit".
According to Kinna, anarcho-capitalists "will sometimes label
themselves market anarchists because they recognize the negative
connotations of 'capitalism'. But the literature of anarcho-capitalism
draws on classical liberal theory, particularly the Austrian School –
Friedrich von Hayek and Ludwig von Mises – rather than recognizable
anarchist traditions. Ayn Rand's laissez-faire, anti-government,
corporate philosophy – Objectivism – is sometimes associated with
anarcho-capitalism".[38] Other scholars similarly associate
anarcho-capitalism with anti-state classical liberalism, neo-classical
liberalism, radical neoliberalism and
right-libertarianism.[26][104][30][140]
Paul Dragos Aligica writes that there is a "foundational difference
between the classical liberal and the anarcho-capitalist positions".
Classical liberalism, while accepting critical arguments against
collectivism, acknowledges a certain level of public ownership and
collective governance as necessary to provide practical solutions to
political problems. In contrast anarcho-capitalism, according to
Aligica, denies any requirement for any form of public administration,
and allows no meaningful role for the public sphere, which is seen as
sub-optimal and illegitimate.[141]
Individualist anarchism
Main article: Individualist anarchism
Lysander Spooner, an American individualist anarchist and mutualist,
who is claimed to have influenced anarcho-capitalism
Murray Rothbard, a student of Ludwig von Mises, stated that he was
influenced by the work of the 19th-century American individualist
anarchists.[142] In the winter of 1949, Rothbard decided to reject
minimal state laissez-faire and embrace his interpretation of
individualist anarchism.[143] In 1965, Rothbard wrote that "Lysander
Spooner and Benjamin R. Tucker were unsurpassed as political
philosophers and nothing is more needed today than a revival and
development of the largely forgotten legacy they left to political
philosophy".[144] However, Rothbard thought that they had a faulty
understanding of economics as the 19th-century individualist
anarchists had a labor theory of value as influenced by the classical
economists and was a student of Austrian School economics which does
not agree with the labor theory of value.[14] Rothbard sought to meld
19th-century American individualist anarchists' advocacy of economic
individualism and free markets with the principles of Austrian School
economics, arguing that "[t]here is, in the body of thought known as
'Austrian economics', a scientific explanation of the workings of the
free market (and of the consequences of government intervention in
that market) which individualist anarchists could easily incorporate
into their political and social Weltanschauung".[145] Rothbard held
that the economic consequences of the political system they advocate
would not result in an economy with people being paid in proportion to
labor amounts, nor would profit and interest disappear as they
expected. Tucker thought that unregulated banking and money issuance
would cause increases in the money supply so that interest rates would
drop to zero or near to it.[144] Peter Marshall states that
"anarcho-capitalism overlooks the egalitarian implications of
traditional individualist anarchists like Spooner and Tucker".[26]
Stephanie Silberstein states that "While Spooner was no free-market
capitalist, nor an anarcho-capitalist, he was not as opposed to
capitalism as most socialists were."[146]
In "The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine: An Economist's View", Rothbard
explained his disagreements. Rothbard disagreed with Tucker that it
would cause the money supply to increase because he believed that the
money supply in a free market would be self-regulating. If it were
not, then Rothbard argued inflation would occur so it is not
necessarily desirable to increase the money supply in the first place.
Rothbard claimed that Tucker was wrong to think that interest would
disappear regardless because he believed people, in general, do not
wish to lend their money to others without compensation, so there is
no reason why this would change just because banking was
unregulated.[144] Tucker held a labor theory of value and thought that
in a free market people would be paid in proportion to how much labor
they exerted and that exploitation or usury was taking place if they
were not. As Tucker explained in State Socialism and Anarchism, his
theory was that unregulated banking would cause more money to be
available and that this would allow the proliferation of new
businesses which would, in turn, raise demand for labor.[147] This led
Tucker to believe that the labor theory of value would be vindicated
and equal amounts of labor would receive equal pay. As an Austrian
School economist, Rothbard did not agree with the labor theory and
believed that prices of goods and services are proportional to
marginal utility rather than to labor amounts in the free market. As
opposed to Tucker he did not think that there was anything
exploitative about people receiving an income according to how much
"buyers of their services value their labor" or what that labor
produces.[144]
Benjamin Tucker, another individualist anarchist, who identified as a
socialist and his individualist anarchism as anarchistic socialism
versus state socialism, said to have influenced anarcho-capitalism
Without the labor theory of value,[47] some argue that 19th-century
individualist anarchists approximate the modern movement of
anarcho-capitalism,[14][15][16] although this has been contested[28]
or rejected.[148][149][150] As economic theory changed, the popularity
of the labor theory of classical economics was superseded by the
subjective theory of value of neoclassical economics and Rothbard
combined Mises' Austrian School of economics with the absolutist views
of human rights and rejection of the state he had absorbed from
studying the individualist American anarchists of the 19th century
such as Tucker and Spooner.[151] In the mid-1950s, Rothbard wrote an
unpublished article named "Are Libertarians 'Anarchists'?" under the
pseudonym "Aubrey Herbert", concerned with differentiating himself
from communist and socialistic economic views of anarchists, including
the individualist anarchists of the 19th century, concluding that "we
are not anarchists and that those who call us anarchists are not on
firm etymological ground and are being completely unhistorical. On the
other hand, it is clear that we are not archists either: we do not
believe in establishing a tyrannical central authority that will
coerce the noninvasive as well as the invasive. Perhaps, then, we
could call ourselves by a new name: nonarchist."[152] Joe Peacott, an
American individualist anarchist in the mutualist tradition,
criticizes anarcho-capitalists for trying to hegemonize the
individualist anarchism label and make appear as if all individualist
anarchists are in favor of capitalism.[149] Peacott states that
"individualists, both past and present, agree with the communist
anarchists that present-day capitalism is based on economic coercion,
not on voluntary contract. Rent and interest are the mainstays of
modern capitalism and are protected and enforced by the state. Without
these two unjust institutions, capitalism could not exist".[153]
Anarchist activists and scholars do not consider anarcho-capitalism as
a part of the anarchist movement because anarchism has historically
been an anti-capitalist movement and see it as incompatible with
capitalist forms.[156] Although some regard anarcho-capitalism as a
form of individualist anarchism,[14][15][16] many others disagree or
contest the existence of an individualist–socialist divide because
individualist anarchism is largely libertarian socialist.[28][157] In
coming to terms that anarchists mostly identified with socialism,
Rothbard wrote that individualist anarchism is different from
anarcho-capitalism and other capitalist theories due to the
individualist anarchists retaining the labor theory of value and
socialist doctrines.[152] Similarly, many writers deny that
anarcho-capitalism is a form of anarchism or that capitalism is
compatible with anarchism.[158]
The Palgrave Handbook of Anarchism writes that "[a]s Benjamin Franks
rightly points out, individualisms that defend or reinforce
hierarchical forms such as the economic-power relations of
anarcho-capitalism are incompatible with practices of social anarchism
based on developing immanent goods which contest such as
inequalities". Laurence Davis cautiosly asks "[I]s anarcho-capitalism
really a form of anarchism or instead a wholly different ideological
paradigm whose adherents have attempted to expropriate the language of
anarchism for their own anti-anarchist ends?" Davis cites Iain McKay,
"whom Franks cites as an authority to support his contention that
'academic analysis has followed activist currents in rejecting the
view that anarcho-capitalism has anything to do with social
anarchism'", as arguing "quite emphatically on the very pages cited by
Franks that anarcho-capitalism is by no means a type of anarchism".
McKay writes that "[i]t is important to stress that anarchist
opposition to the so-called capitalist 'anarchists' does not reflect
some kind of debate within anarchism, as many of these types like to
pretend, but a debate between anarchism and its old enemy capitalism.
... Equally, given that anarchists and 'anarcho'-capitalists have
fundamentally different analyses and goals it is hardly 'sectarian' to
point this out".[120]
Davis writes that "Franks asserts without supporting evidence that
most major forms of individualist anarchism have been largely
anarcho-capitalist in content, and concludes from this premise that
most forms of individualism are incompatible with anarchism". Davis
argues that "the conclusion is unsustainable because the premise is
false, depending as it does for any validity it might have on the
further assumption that anarcho-capitalism is indeed a form of
anarchism. If we reject this view, then we must also reject the
individual anarchist versus the communal anarchist 'chasm' style of
argument that follows from it".[120] Davis maintains that "the
ideological core of anarchism is the belief that society can and
should be organised without hierarchy and domination. Historically,
anarchists have struggles against a wide range of regimes of
domination, from capitalism, the state system, patriarchy,
heterosexism, and the domination of nature to colonialism, the war
system, slavery, fascism, white supremacy, and certain forms of
organised religion". According to Davis, "[w]hile these visions range
from the predominantly individualistic to the predominantly
communitarian, features common to virtually all include an emphasis on
self-management and self-regulatory methods of organisation, voluntary
association, decentralised society, based on the principle of free
association, in which people will manage and govern themselves".[120]
Finally, Davis includes a footnote stating that "[i]ndividualist
anarchism may plausibly be re regarded as a form of both socialism and
anarchism. Whether the individualist anarchists were consistent
anarchists (and socialists) is another question entirely. ... McKay
comments as follows: 'any individualist anarchism which supports wage
labour is inconsistent anarchism. It can easily be made consistent
anarchism by applying its own principles consistenly [sic?]. In
contrast 'anarcho'-capitalism rejects so many of the basic,
underlying, principles of anarchism ... that it cannot be made
consistent with the ideals of anarchism'".[120]
Historical precedents
Several anarcho-capitalists and right-libertarians have discussed
historical precedents of what they believe were examples of
anarcho-capitalism.[159]
Free cities of medieval Europe
Economist and libertarian scholar Bryan Caplan considers the free
cities of medieval Europe as examples of "anarchist" or "nearly
anarchistic" societies,[20] further arguing:
One case that has inspired both sorts of anarchists is that of the
free cities of medieval Europe. The first weak link in the chain of
feudalism, these free cities became Europe's centers of economic
development, trade, art, and culture. They provided a haven for
runaway serfs, who could often legally gain their freedom if they
avoided re-capture for a year and a day. And they offer many examples
of how people can form mutual-aid associations for protection,
insurance, and community. Of course, left-anarchists and
anarcho-capitalists take a somewhat different perspective on the free
cities: the former emphasize the communitarian and egalitarian
concerns of the free cities, while the latter point to the relatively
unregulated nature of their markets and the wide range of services
(often including defense, security, and legal services) which were
provided privately or semi-privately.[20]
Medieval Iceland
19th-century interpretation of the Althing in the Icelandic
Commonwealth which authors such as David D. Friedman believe to have
some features of anarcho-capitalist society
According to the libertarian theorist David D. Friedman, "[m]edieval
Icelandic institutions have several peculiar and interesting
characteristics; they might almost have been invented by a mad
economist to test the lengths to which market systems could supplant
government in its most fundamental functions".[21] While not directly
labeling it anarcho-capitalist, Friedman argues that the legal system
of the Icelandic Commonwealth comes close to being a real-world
anarcho-capitalist legal system.[160] Although noting that there was a
single legal system, Friedman argues that enforcement of the law was
entirely private and highly capitalist, providing some evidence of how
such a society would function. Friedman further wrote that "[e]ven
where the Icelandic legal system recognized an essentially 'public'
offense, it dealt with it by giving some individual (in some cases
chosen by lot from those affected) the right to pursue the case and
collect the resulting fine, thus fitting it into an essentially
private system".[21]
American Old West
According to Terry L. Anderson and P. J. Hill, the Old West in the
United States in the period of 1830 to 1900 was similar to
anarcho-capitalism in that "private agencies provided the necessary
basis for an orderly society in which property was protected and
conflicts were resolved" and that the common popular perception that
the Old West was chaotic with little respect for property rights is
incorrect.[161] Since squatters had no claim to western lands under
federal law, extra-legal organizations formed to fill the void. Benson
explains:
The land clubs and claim associations each adopted their own
written contract setting out the laws that provided the means for
defining and protecting property rights in the land. They established
procedures for registration of land claims, as well as for the
protection of those claims against outsiders, and for adjudication of
internal disputes that arose. The reciprocal arrangements for
protection would be maintained only if a member complied with the
association's rules and its court's rulings. Anyone who refused would
be ostracized. A boycott by a land club meant that an individual had
no protection against aggression other than what he could provide
himself.[162]
According to Anderson, "[d]efining anarcho-capitalist to mean minimal
government with property rights developed from the bottom up, the
western frontier was anarcho-capitalistic. People on the frontier
invented institutions that fit the resource constraints they
faced".[163]
Gaelic Ireland
In his work For a New Liberty, Murray Rothbard has claimed ancient
Gaelic Ireland as an example of nearly anarcho-capitalist society.[19]
In his depiction, citing the work of Professor Joseph Peden,[164] the
basic political unit of ancient Ireland was the tuath, which is
portrayed as "a body of persons voluntarily united for socially
beneficial purposes" with its territorial claim being limited to "the
sum total of the landed properties of its members".[19] Civil disputes
were settled by private arbiters called "brehons" and the compensation
to be paid to the wronged party was insured through voluntary surety
relationships. Commenting on the "kings" of tuaths,[19] Rothbard
stated:
The king was elected by the tuath from within a royal kin group
(the derbfine), which carried the hereditary priestly function.
Politically, however, the king had strictly limited functions: he was
the military leader of the tuath, and he presided over the tuath
assemblies. But he could only conduct war or peace negotiations as an
agent of the assemblies, and he was in no sense sovereign and had no
rights of administering justice over tuath members. He could not
legislate, and when he himself was party to a lawsuit, he had to
submit his case to an independent judicial arbiter.[19]
Law merchant, admiralty law, and early common law
Some libertarians have cited law merchant, admiralty law and early
common law as examples of anarcho-capitalism.[165][166][failed
verification][167]
In his work Power and Market,[43] Rothbard stated:
The law merchant, admiralty law, and much of the common law began
to be developed by privately competitive judges, who were sought out
by litigants for their expertise in understanding the legal areas
involved. The fairs of Champagne and the great marts of international
trade in the Middle Ages enjoyed freely competitive courts, and people
could patronize those that they deemed most accurate and
efficient.[43]: 1051
Somalia from 1991 to 2006
Main article: History of Somalia (1991–2006)
Economist Alex Tabarrok argued that Somalia in its stateless period
provided a "unique test of the theory of anarchy", in some aspects
near of that espoused by anarcho-capitalists David D. Friedman and
Murray Rothbard.[23] Nonetheless, both anarchists and some
anarcho-capitalists argue that Somalia was not an anarchist
society.[168][169]
Criticism
State, justice and defense
Anarchists such as Brian Morris argue that anarcho-capitalism does not
in fact get rid of the state. He says that anarcho-capitalists "simply
replaced the state with private security firms, and can hardly be
described as anarchists as the term is normally understood".[170] In
"Libertarianism: Bogus Anarchy", anarchist Peter Sabatini notes:
Within Libertarianism, Rothbard represents a minority perspective
that actually argues for the total elimination of the state. However,
Rothbard's claim as an anarchist is quickly voided when it is shown
that he only wants an end to the public state. In its place he allows
countless private states, with each person supplying their own police
force, army, and law, or else purchasing these services from
capitalist vendors. ... Rothbard sees nothing at all wrong with the
amassing of wealth, therefore those with more capital will inevitably
have greater coercive force at their disposal, just as they do
now.[171]
Similarly, Bob Black argues that an anarcho-capitalist wants to
"abolish the state to his own satisfaction by calling it something
else". He states that they do not denounce what the state does, they
just "object to who's doing it".[172]
Paul Birch argues that legal disputes involving several jurisdictions
and different legal systems will be too complex and costly. He
therefore argues that anarcho-capitalism is inherently unstable, and
would evolve, entirely through the operation of free market forces,
into either a single dominant private court with a natural monopoly of
justice over the territory (a de facto state), a society of multiple
city states, each with a territorial monopoly, or a 'pure anarchy'
that would rapidly descend into chaos.[173]
Randall G. Holcombe argues that anarcho-capitalism turns justice into
a commodity as private defense and court firms would favour those who
pay more for their services.[174] He argues that defense agencies
could form cartels and oppress people without fear of
competition.[174] Philosopher Albert Meltzer argued that since
anarcho-capitalism promotes the idea of private armies, it actually
supports a "limited State". He contends that it "is only possible to
conceive of Anarchism which is free, communistic and offering no
economic necessity for repression of countering it".[175]
Robert Nozick argues that a competitive legal system would evolve
toward a monopoly government—even without violating individuals'
rights in the process.[176] In Anarchy, State, and Utopia, Nozick
argues that an anarcho-capitalist society would inevitably transform
into a minarchist state through the eventual emergence of a
monopolistic private defense and judicial agency that no longer faces
competition. He argues that anarcho-capitalism results in an unstable
system that would not endure in the real world. While
anarcho-capitalists such as Roy Childs and Murray Rothbard have
rejected Nozick's arguments,[177] with Rothbard arguing that the
process described by Nozick, with the dominant protection agency
outlawing its competitors, in fact violates its own clients'
rights,[178] John Jefferson actually advocates Nozick's argument and
states that such events would best operate in laissez-faire.[179]
Robert Ellickson presented a Hayekian case against anarcho-capitalism,
calling it a "pipe-dream" and stating that anarcho-capitalists "by
imagining a stable system of competing private associations, ignore
both the inevitability of territorial monopolists in governance, and
the importance of institutions to constrain those monopolists'
abuses".[180]
Rights and freedom
Negative and positive rights are rights that oblige either action
(positive rights) or inaction (negative rights). Anarcho-capitalists
believe that negative rights should be recognized as legitimate, but
positive rights should be rejected as an intrusion. Some critics
reject the distinction between positive and negative rights.[181]
Peter Marshall also states that the anarcho-capitalist definition of
freedom is entirely negative and that it cannot guarantee the positive
freedom of individual autonomy and independence.[26]
About anarcho-capitalism, anarcho-syndicalist and anti-capitalist
intellectual Noam Chomsky says:
Anarcho-capitalism, in my opinion, is a doctrinal system that, if
ever implemented, would lead to forms of tyranny and oppression that
have few counterparts in human history. There isn't the slightest
possibility that its (in my view, horrendous) ideas would be
implemented because they would quickly destroy any society that made
this colossal error. The idea of "free contract" between the potentate
and his starving subject is a sick joke, perhaps worth some moments in
an academic seminar exploring the consequences of (in my view, absurd)
ideas, but nowhere else.[182]
Economics and property
Social anarchists argue that anarcho-capitalism allows individuals to
accumulate significant power through free markets and private
property.[7]
Anarchists argue that certain capitalist transactions are not
voluntary and that maintaining the class structure of a capitalist
society requires coercion which violates anarchist
principles.[183][184][185][186] Anthropologist David Graeber noted his
skepticism about anarcho-capitalism along the same lines, arguing:
To be honest, I'm pretty skeptical about the idea of
anarcho-capitalism. If a-caps imagine a world divided into
property-holding employers and property-less wage laborers, but with
no systematic coercive mechanisms[;] well, I just can't see how it
would work. You always see a-caps saying "if I want to hire someone to
pick my tomatoes, how are you going to stop me without using
coercion?" Notice how you never see anyone say "if I want to hire
myself out to pick someone else's tomatoes, how are you going to stop
me?" Historically nobody ever did wage labor like that if they had
pretty much [any] other option.[187]
Some critics argue that the anarcho-capitalist concept of voluntary
choice ignores constraints due to both human and non-human factors
such as the need for food and shelter as well as active restriction of
both used and unused resources by those enforcing property
claims.[188] If a person requires employment in order to feed and
house himself, the employer-employee relationship could be considered
involuntary. Another criticism is that employment is involuntary
because the economic system that makes it necessary for some
individuals to serve others is supported by the enforcement of
coercive private property relations.[188] Some philosophies view any
ownership claims on land and natural resources as immoral and
illegitimate.[189] Objectivist philosopher Harry Binswanger criticizes
anarcho-capitalism by arguing that "capitalism requires government",
questioning who or what would enforce treaties and contracts.[190]
Some right-libertarian critics of anarcho-capitalism who support the
full privatization of capital such as geolibertarians argue that land
and the raw materials of nature remain a distinct factor of production
and cannot be justly converted to private property because they are
not products of human labor. Some socialists, including market
anarchists and mutualists, adamantly oppose absentee ownership.
Anarcho-capitalists have strong abandonment criteria, namely that one
maintains ownership until one agrees to trade or gift it. Anti-state
critics of this view posit comparatively weak abandonment criteria,
arguing that one loses ownership when one stops personally occupying
and using it as well as the idea of perpetually binding original
appropriation is anathema to traditional schools of anarchism.[173]
Literature
The following is a partial list of notable nonfiction works discussing
anarcho-capitalism.
Bruce L. Benson, The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without The State
To Serve and Protect: Privatization and Community in Criminal Justice
David D. Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom
Edward P. Stringham, Anarchy and the Law: The Political Economy of Choice
George H. Smith, "Justice Entrepreneurship in a Free Market"
Gerard Casey, Libertarian Anarchy: Against the State
Hans-Hermann Hoppe, Anarcho-Capitalism: An Annotated Bibliography
A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism
Democracy: The God That Failed
The Economics and Ethics of Private Property
Linda and Morris Tannehill, The Market for Liberty
Michael Huemer, The Problem of Political Authority
Murray Rothbard, founder of anarcho-capitalism:
For a New Liberty
Man, Economy, and State
Power and Market
The Ethics of Liberty
See also
Agorism
Anarchapulco
Anarcho-capitalism and minarchism
Consequentialist libertarianism
Counter-economics
Creative disruption
Crypto-anarchism
Dark Enlightenment
Definition of anarchism and libertarianism
Issues in anarchism
Left-wing market anarchism
Natural-rights libertarianism
Privatization in criminal justice
Propertarianism
Stateless society
The Libertarian Forum
Voluntaryism
References
Rothbard, Murray N., The Betrayal of the American Right (2007): 188
"Flags of political parties (Sweden)". FOTW Flags of the World
website. Retrieved 30 October 2014.
"ancap", Wiktionary, 9 February 2022, retrieved 7 May 2022
"ANCAP | Definition of ANCAP by Oxford Dictionary on Lexico.com
also meaning of ANCAP". Lexico Dictionaries | English. Archived from
the original on 15 May 2021. Retrieved 15 May 2021.
Morriss, Andrew P. (15 August 2008). "Anarcho-Capitalism".
Libertarianism.org. Retrieved 21 August 2022. "Although most
anarchists oppose all large institutions, public or private,
anarcho-capitalists oppose the state, but not private actors with
significant market power."
Geloso, Vincent; Leeson, Peter T. (2020). "Are Anarcho-Capitalists
Insane? Medieval Icelandic Conflict Institutions in Comparative
Perspective". Revue d'economie politique. 130 (6): 957–974.
doi:10.3917/redp.306.0115. ISSN 0373-2630. S2CID 235008718.
"Anarcho-capitalism is a variety of libertarianism according to which
all government institutions can and should be replaced by private
ones."
Morriss, Andrew (2008). "Anarcho-Capitalism". In Hamowy, Ronald
(ed.). The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. Thousand Oaks, California:
SAGE; Cato Institute. pp. 13–14. doi:10.4135/9781412965811.n8. ISBN
978-1-4129-6580-4. OCLC 750831024.
Stringham, Edward (2007). Anarchy and the law: the political
economy of choice. p. 51. ISBN 9781412805797.
Marshall, Peter. "The New Right and Anarcho-capitalism". Retrieved
2 July 2020.
Murphy, Ryan H. (2019). Markets against Modernity: Ecological
Irrationality, Public and Private. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 84. ISBN
978-1498591188.
Hatlestad, Luc (19 August 2018). "Is Anarchy the Solution to Our
Political Problems?". 5280 Denver's Mile High Magazine.
Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (31 December 2001). "Anarcho-Capitalism: An
Annotated Bibliography". Lew Rockwell.com. Retrieved 5 July 2020.
Leeson, Robert (2017). Hayek: A Collaborative Biography, Part IX:
The Divine Right of the 'Free' Market. Springer. p. 180. ISBN
978-3-319-60708-5. "To the original 'anarchocapitalist' (Rothbard
coined the term) [...]."
Miller, David; et al., eds. (1987). Blackwell Encyclopaedia of
Political Thought. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. p. 290. ISBN
978-0-631-17944-3. "A student and disciple of the Austrian economist
Ludwig von Mises, Rothbard combined the laissez-faire economics of his
teacher with the absolutist views of human rights and rejection of the
state he had absorbed from studying the individualist American
anarchists of the 19th century such as Lysander Spooner and Benjamin
Tucker."
Bottomore, Tom (1991). "Anarchism". A Dictionary of Marxist
Thought. Oxford: Blackwell Reference. p. 21. ISBN 0-63118082-6.
Outhwaite, William (2003). "Anarchism". The Blackwell Dictionary
of Modern Social Thought. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. p. 13. ISBN
9780631221647. "Their successors today, such as Murray Rothbard,
having abandoned the labor theory of value, describe themselves as
anarcho-capitalists."
Rothbard, Murray (1978). "12 The Public Sector, III: Police, Law,
and the Courts". For a New Liberty. Auburn: Mises Institute. p. 282.
ISBN 9781610164481.
Rothbard, Murray (Spring 1982). "Law, Property Rights, and Air
Pollution". Cato Journal. 2 (1): 55–99.
Rothbard, Murray (1978). For a New Liberty. Auburn: Mises
Institute. p. 282. ISBN 978-1-61016-448-1.
"Anarchist Theory FAQ Version 5.2". George Mason University.
Retrieved 23 August 2020.
Friedman, David D. (1979). "Private Creation and Enforcement of
Law: A Historical Case". Retrieved 12 August 2005.
Long, Roderick T. (6 June 2002). "Privatization, Viking Style:
Model or Misfortune? (The Vikings Were Libertarians)".
LewRockwell.com. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
Tabarrok, Alex (21 April 2004). "Somalia and the theory of
anarchy". Marginal Revolution. Retrieved 13 January 2008.
[19][20][21][22][23]
Long, Roderick T.; Machan, Tibor R., eds. (2008).
Anarchism/Minarchism: Is a Government Part of a Free Country?.
Ashgate. ISBN 978-0-7546-6066-8.
Marshall, Peter (1992). Demanding the Impossible: A History of
Anarchism. London: HarperCollins. pp. 564–565. ISBN 978-0-00-217855-6.
"Anarcho-capitalists are against the State simply because they are
capitalists first and foremost. [...] They are not concerned with the
social consequences of capitalism for the weak, powerless and
ignorant. [...] As such, anarcho-capitalism overlooks the egalitarian
implications of traditional individualist anarchists like Spooner and
Tucker. In fact, few anarchists would accept the 'anarcho-capitalists'
into the anarchist camp since they do not share a concern for economic
equality and social justice. Their self-interested, calculating market
men would be incapable of practising voluntary cooperation and mutual
aid. Anarcho-capitalists, even if they do reject the state, might
therefore best be called right-wing libertarians rather than
anarchists."
Jennings, Jeremy (1993). "Anarchism". In Eatwell, Roger; Wright,
Anthony (eds.). Contemporary Political Ideologies. London: Pinter. pp.
127–146. ISBN 978-0-86187-096-7. "[...] anarchism does not stand for
the untrammelled freedom of the individual (as the
'anarcho-capitalists' appear to believe) but, as we have already seen,
for the extension of individuality and community" (p. 143).
Franks, Benjamin (August 2013). Freeden, Michael; Stears, Marc
(eds.). "Anarchism". The Oxford Handbook of Political Ideologies.
Oxford University Press: 385–404.
doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199585977.013.0001. "Individualisms that
defend or reinforce hierarchical forms such as the economic-power
relations of anarcho-capitalism [...] are incompatible with practices
of social anarchism. [...] Increasingly, academic analysis has
followed activist currents in rejecting the view that
anarcho-capitalism has anything to do with social anarchism" (pp.
393–394).
Meltzer, Albert (2000). Anarchism: Arguments for and Against.
London: AK Press. p. 50. ISBN 978-1-873176-57-3. "The philosophy of
'anarcho-capitalism' dreamed up by the 'libertarian' New Right, has
nothing to do with Anarchism as known by the Anarchist movement
proper."
Newman, Saul (2010). The Politics of Postanarchism. Edinburgh
University Press. p. 43. "It is important to distinguish between
anarchism and certain strands of right-wing libertarianism which at
times go by the same name (for example, Rothbard's
anarcho-capitalism)." ISBN 0748634959.
White, Richard; Williams, Colin (2014). "Anarchist Economic
Practices in a 'Capitalist' Society: Some Implications for
Organisation and the Future of Work". Ephermera: Theory and Politics
in Organization. 14 (4): 947–971. SSRN 2707308.
Marshall, Peter H. (2010). Demanding the impossible : a history of
anarchism : be realistic! Demand the impossible!. Oakland, CA: PM
Press. pp. 564–565. ISBN 978-1-60486-268-3. OCLC 611612065.
Gay, Kathlyn; Gay, Martin (1999). Encyclopedia of Political
Anarchy. ABC-CLIO. p. 15. ISBN 978-0-87436-982-3. "For many anarchists
(of whatever persuasion), anarcho-capitalism is a contradictory term,
since 'traditional' anarchists oppose capitalism".
Vincent, Andrew (2009). Modern Political Ideologies (3rd ed.).
Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons. p. 66. ISBN 978-1-4443-1105-1. "Whom to
include under the rubric of the New Right remains puzzling. It is
usually seen as an amalgam of traditional liberal conservatism,
Austrian liberal economic theory (Ludwing von Mises and Hayek),
extreme libertarianism (anarcho-capitalism), and crude populism."
J Michael Oliver (2013). The New Libertarianism:
Anarcho-Capitalism. pp. 11–12. ISBN 978-1491068625.
Duggan, Lisa (22 May 2019). "Ayn Rand and the Cruel Heart of
Neoliberalism". Dissent Magazine. Retrieved 29 October 2021.
Patrik Schumacher (2016). "The Stages of Capitalism and the Styles
of Architecture". ASA web-magazine. Retrieved 22 December 2020.
Kinna, Ruth, ed. (2012). The Bloomsbury Companion to Anarchism.
New York: Bloomsbury Publishing USA. pp. 330–331. ISBN 9781441142702.
David Friedman (27 November 2012). David Friedman on How to
Privatize Everything (YouTube). ReasonTV. Archived from the original
on 22 November 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2021.
Roberta Modugno Crocetta, Murray Rothbard's anarcho-capitalism in
the contemporary debate. A critical defense, Ludwig Von Mises
Institute.
Michael Oliver, "Exclusive Interview With Murray Rothbard",
originally published in The New Banner: A Fortnightly Libertarian
Journal, 25 February 1972. For an earlier published use of
anarcho-capitalism by Rothbard, see his "Know Your Rights" WIN: Peace
and Freedom through Nonviolent Action, Volume 7, No. 4, 1 March 1971,
6–10.
Rothbard, Murray N., A Future of Peace and Capitalism; Murray N.
Rothbard, Left and Right: The Prospects for Liberty.
Rothbard, Murray (1977) [1970]. Power and Market (2nd ed.).
published in Rothbard, Murray (2009). Man, Economy, and State with
Power and Market (2nd ed.). Mises Institute. ISBN 978-1-933550-27-5.
Retrieved 15 June 2020.
Linda and Morris Tannehill. The Market for Liberty, p. 81.
"Libertarianism" (2007). In Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 30 July 2007.
Murray Rothbard (2000). "Egalitarianism as A Revolt Against Nature
And Other Essays: and other essays". Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2000.
p. 207.
Avrich, Paul (1996). Anarchist Voices: An Oral History of
Anarchism in America (abridged paperback ed.). Princeton: Princeton
University Press. p. 282. ISBN 9780691044941. "Although there are many
honorable exceptions who still embrace the 'socialist' label, most
people who call themselves individualist anarchists today are
followers of Murray Rothbard's Austrian economics and have abandoned
the labor theory of value."
Carson, Kevin (2006). Studies in Mutualist Political Economy.
"Preface". Archived 15 April 2011 at the Wayback Machine Charleston:
BookSurge Publishing. ISBN 9781419658693. "Murray N. Rothbard
(1926–1995), American economist, historian, and individualist
anarchist."
Edwards, Maverick (9 January 2021). "The Failure of Imagination: A
Theoretical and Pragmatic Analysis of Utopianism as an Orientation for
Human Life". Liberty University Journal of Statesmanship & Public
Policy. 1 (2). Retrieved 16 January 2022.
Stanisław Wójtowicz (2017). "Anarcho-capitalism, or can we do away
with the state". Nauka (4). ISSN 1231-8515. "The last problem is
especially vexing, since anarcho-capitalists seem to be caught up in a
contradiction here. On one hand, they are proponents of a specific
moral theory (based on non-aggression principle), on the other hand,
they do not allow for any central, monopolistic agency to impose that
moral theory on society."
Friedman, David D. (1989) "Chapter 41: Problems". The Machinery of
Freedom: Guide to a Radical Capitalism (2nd ed.). La Salle: Open Court
Press. ISBN 0-8126-9069-9.
Rothbard, Murray (1982). The Ethics of Liberty. Atlantic
Highlands: Humanities Press. p. 162. ISBN 978-0-8147-7506-6.
Rothbard, Murray N. (1975) "Society Without A State" Libertarian
Forum newsletter (January 1975).
Rothbard, Murray (25 February 1972). "Exclusive Interview With
Murray Rothbard". The New Banner: A Fortnightly Libertarian Journal.
Retrieved 10 September 2020.
Cristóbal Matarán López (2021). "The Austrian school of Madrid".
The Review of Austrian Economics. doi:10.1007/s11138-021-00541-0. "In
addition, Professor Huerta de Soto has become one of the most
prominent and resolute defenders of the Anarchocapitalism, that is,
the full and complete privatisation of all goods and services."
Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (20 May 2002). "Rothbardian Ethics".
LewRockwell.com. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
Hall, Larry M., "Anarcho-Capitalist Threads in Modern
Libertarianism: The Social Thought of Murray Rothbard." PhD diss., p.
126, University of Tennessee, 1990.
John Locke, Second Treatise of Government, Chapter V, paragraph 27.
Stephanie Silberstein. "Was Spooner Really an Anarcho-Socialist?".
Anarchy Archives. Archived from the original on 25 April 2017.
Retrieved 5 July 2020.
Rothbard, Murray (1993) [1962]. Man, Economy, and State (2nd ed.).
published in Rothbard, Murray (2009). Man, Economy, and State with
Power and Market (2nd ed.). Mises Institute. ISBN 978-1-933550-27-5.
Retrieved 15 June 2020.
Rothbard, Murray (2000). "Justice and Property Rights: The Failure
of Utilitarianism". In Egalitarianism as a Revolt Against Nature and
Other Essays (2nd ed.). Auburn: Mises Institute. p. 113. ISBN
9781610164627.
Cobin, John M. (2009). A Primer on Modern Themes in Free Market
Economics and Policy. Irvine: Universal-Publishers. p. 557. ISBN
9781610167024.
Deist, Jeff (7 December 2019). "Rothbard on Slavery Reparations".
Mises Institute. Retrieved 6 September 2020.
Gordon, David, ed.; Rothbard, Murray; Fuller, Edward W. (2019).
Rothbard A to Z. Auburn: Mises Institute. ISBN 9781610167024.
Carson, Kevin (28 September 2012). "The Left-Rothbardians, Part I:
Rothbard". Center for a Stateless Society. "What most people
ordinarily identify as the stereotypical 'libertarian' privatization
proposal, unfortunately, goes something like this: sell it to a giant
corporation on terms that are most advantageous to the corporation.
Rothbard proposed, instead, was to treat state property as unowned,
and allow it to be homesteaded by those actually occupying it and
mixing their labor with it. This would mean transforming government
utilities, schools, and other services into consumer cooperatives and
placing them under the direct control of their present clientele. It
would mean handing over state industry to workers' syndicates and
transforming it into worker-owned cooperatives". Retrieved 10 January
2020.
Rothbard, Murray (Spring 1965). "Left and Right: The Prospects for
Liberty". Left and Right: A Journal of Libertarian Thought. 1 (1):
4–22.
Long, Roderick T. (8 April 2006). "Rothbard's 'Left and Right':
Forty Years Later". Mises Institute. Rothbard Memorial Lecture,
Austrian Scholars Conference 2006. Retrieved 17 March 2020.
Hess, Karl (15 June 1969). "Letter From Washington: Where Are The
Specifics?". The Libertarian Forum. I (VI): 2. published in Rothbard,
Murray N., ed. (2006). The Complete Libertarian Forum: 1969–1984
(PDF). Vol. 1: 1969–1975. Ludwig von Mises Institute. p. 26. ISBN
978-1-933550-02-2. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph (1840). What is Property?
Murray Rothbard. "Concepts of the role of intellectuals in social
change toward laissez faire" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF)
on 16 December 2008. Retrieved 28 December 2008.
Weick, David. Anarchist Justice. pp. 223–24
Sabatini, Peter. Libertarianism: Bogus Anarchy.
Kropotkin, Peter. Anarchism.
Stacy, Don (2011). "Review of Kosanke's Instead of Politics – Don
Stacy". Libertarian Papers. 3 (3).
Sandra Jeppesen; Anna Kruzynski; Rachel Sarrasin (2014). "The
anarchist commons" (PDF). Ephemera.
Holcombe, Randall G. (Spring 2005). "Common Property in
Anarcho-Capitalism" (PDF). Journal of Libertarian Studies. 19 (2):
3–29. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
Avrich, Paul. Anarchist Voices: An Oral History of Anarchism in
America, Abridged Paperback Edition (1996), p. 282.
Kinsella, N. Stephan (2008). Against Intellectual Property (PDF).
Ludwig Von Mises Institute.
Zaheer Kazmi (2012). Polite Anarchy in International Relations
Theory. The Palgrave Macmillan History of International Thought.
Palgrave Macmillan US. p. 46. ISBN 978-1-137-02813-6. "Notably, in
light of latter-day anarcho-capitalism, Tucker had also advocated the
privatisation of the policing and security functions of the state to
protect people and property and accepted the use of violence as means
of enforcing contracts."
Nathan W. Schlueter; Nikolai G. Wenzel (2018). Selfish
Libertarians and Socialist Conservatives?. Stanford University Press.
p. 138. ISBN 978-1-5036-0029-4.
Carl Levy; Matthew Adams (2019). The Palgrave Handbook of
Anarchism. Palgrave Macmillan. p. 558. ISBN 978-3-319-75620-2.
Murray Rothbard (4 May 2007). "Children and Rights". Mises Institute.
"Where did Donald Trump get his racialized rhetoric? From
libertarians". The Washington Post. 2 September 2016.
Nozick, Robert (1974). Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic
Books.[pages needed]
Friedman, David (1973). The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a
Radical Capitalism. Harper & Row. pp. 144–145. ISBN 978-0-06-091010-5.
Brown, Susan Love, The Free Market as Salvation from Government:
The Anarcho-Capitalist View, Meanings of the Market: The Free Market
in Western Culture, edited by James G. Carrier, Berg/Oxford, 1997, p.
113.
Klosko, George (2011). The Oxford Handbook of the History of
Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 684.
Friedman, David. The Machinery of Freedom. Second edition. La
Salle, Ill, Open Court, pp. 116–17.
Friedman, David (1973). The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a
Radical Capitalism. Harper & Row. pp. 127–128. ISBN 978-0-06-091010-5.
De Molinari, Gustave (1849). The Production of Security.
Translated by McCulloch, J. Huston. Archived from the original on 27
September 2007. Retrieved 15 July 2006.
Stringham, Edward; Curott, Nicholas (2010). Lopez, Edward (ed.).
"The Rise of Government Law Enforcement in England". The Pursuit of
Justice: Law and Economics of Legal Institutions. Independent
Institute. SSRN 1711665.
Stringham, Edward (Winter 1998–1999). "Market Chosen Law". Journal
of Libertarian Studies. 14 (1): 53–77. SSRN 1676257.
Stringham, Edward; Zywicki, Todd (5 November 2005). "Rivalry and
Superior Dispatch: An Analysis of Competing Courts in Medieval and
Early Modern England". George Mason Law & Economics Research Paper. 10
(57). doi:10.2139/ssrn.1703598. S2CID 154834118. SSRN 1703598.
Friedman, David (1973). "29". The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a
Radical Capitalism. Harper & Row. ISBN 978-0-06-091010-5. Archived
from the original on 31 December 2010.
Stringham, Edward (2015). Private Governance. Oxford University Press.
Caplan, Bryan; Stringham, Edward (2008). "Privatizing the
Adjudication of Disputes". Theoretical Inquiries in Law. 9 (2):
503–28. doi:10.2202/1565-3404.1195. S2CID 154304272. SSRN 1674441.
Rothbard, Murray N. (February 1973). "Interview Reason". Retrieved
20 August 2005.
Rothbard, Murray (1981). "Konkin on Libertarian Strategy" (PDF).
Strategy of the New Libertarian Alliance.
O'Keeffe, Matthew (1989). "Retribution Versus Restitution" (PDF).
Legal Notes. London: Libertarian Alliance. 5. ISBN 1-870614-22-4. ISSN
0267-7083. Archived from the original (PDF) on 3 February 2022.
Benson, Bruce (1998). To Serve and Protect: Privatization and
Community in Criminal Justice. NYU Press. pp. 235–38. ISBN
978-0-8147-1327-3.
Tannehill, Linda and Morris (1993). The Market for Liberty (PDF).
San Francisco: Fox & Wilkes. pp. 105–106. ISBN 978-0-930073-08-4.
Retrieved 30 June 2011.
Rothbard, Murray (2016). "14. Children's Rights". The Ethics of
Liberty (PDF). New York and London: New York University Press. p. 103.
ISBN 978-1-61016-664-5.
Block, Walter (2 January 1979). "On Baby Selling". Libtertarianism.org.
Goodway, David (2006). Anarchist Seeds Beneath the Snow:
Left-Libertarian Thought and British Writers from William Morris to
Colin Ward. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press. p. 4.
"'Libertarian' and 'libertarianism' are frequently employed by
anarchists as synonyms for 'anarchist' and 'anarchism', largely as an
attempt to distance themselves from the negative connotations of
'anarchy' and its derivatives. The situation has been vastly
complicated in recent decades with the rise of anarcho-capitalism,
'minimal statism' and an extreme right-wing laissez-faire philosophy
advocated by such theorists as Rothbard and Nozick and their adoption
of the words 'libertarian' and 'libertarianism'. It has therefore now
become necessary to distinguish between their right libertarianism and
the left libertarianism of the anarchist tradition."
Jun, Nathan (September 2009). "Anarchist Philosophy and Working
Class Struggle: A Brief History and Commentary". WorkingUSA. 12 (3):
507–508. doi:10.1111/j.1743-4580.2009.00251.x. ISSN 1089-7011.
"[Anarchists oppose] all centralized and hierarchical forms of
government (e.g., monarchy, representative democracy, state socialism,
etc.), economic class systems (e.g., capitalism, Bolshevism,
feudalism, slavery, etc.), autocratic religions (e.g., fundamentalist
Islam, Roman Catholicism, etc.), patriarchy, heterosexism, white
supremacy, and imperialism."
Williams, Dana M. (2018). "Contemporary Anarchist and Anarchistic
Movements". Sociology Compass. Wiley. 12 (6): 4.
doi:10.1111/soc4.12582. ISSN 1751-9020.
Kahn, Joseph (2000). "Anarchism, the Creed That Won't Stay Dead;
The Spread of World Capitalism Resurrects a Long-Dormant Movement".
The New York Times (5 August).
Moynihan, Colin. "Book Fair Unites Anarchists. In Spirit, Anyway".
The New York Times (16 April).
Brooks, Frank H. (1994). The Individualist Anarchists: An
Anthology of Liberty (1881–1908). Transaction Publishers. p. xi. ISBN
1-56000-132-1. "Usually considered to be an extreme left-wing
ideology, anarchism has always included a significant strain of
radical individualism, from the hyperrationalism of Godwin, to the
egoism of Stirner, to the libertarians and anarcho-capitalists of
today".
Guerin, Daniel (1970). Anarchism: From Theory to Practice. Monthly
Review Press. pp. 12, 35. ISBN 9780853451280.
Tame, Chris R. (October 1983). The Chicago School: Lessons from
the Thirties for the Eighties. Economic Affairs. p. 56.
McKay, Iain (2008). An Anarchist FAQ. 1. "What are the myths of
capitalist economics?" "Is 'anarcho'-capitalism a type of anarchism?"
Oakland/Edinburgh: AK Press. ISBN 978-1902593906.
Marshall, Peter (1992). Demanding the Impossible: A History of
Anarchism. London: HarperCollins. p. 641. ISBN 978-0-00-217855-6. "For
a long time, libertarian was interchangeable in France with anarchist
but in recent years, its meaning has become more ambivalent."
Cohn, Jesse (20 April 2009). "Anarchism". In Ness, Immanuel (ed.).
The International Encyclopedia of Revolution and Protest. Oxford: John
Wiley & Sons. pp. 1–11 (6). doi:10.1002/9781405198073.wbierp0039. ISBN
978-1-4051-9807-3. "[...] 'libertarianism' [...] a term that, until
the mid-twentieth century, was synonymous with 'anarchism' per se"
Francis, Mark (December 1983). "Human Rights and Libertarians".
Australian Journal of Politics & History. 29 (3): 462.
doi:10.1111/j.1467-8497.1983.tb00212.x. ISSN 0004-9522.
Francis, Mark (December 1983). "Human Rights and Libertarians".
Australian Journal of Politics & History. 29 (3): 462–463.
doi:10.1111/j.1467-8497.1983.tb00212.x. ISSN 0004-9522.
Gay, Kathlyn; Gay, Martin (1999). Encyclopedia of Political
Anarchy. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-0-87436-982-3.
Morriss, Andrew (2008). "Anarcho-capitalism". In Hamowy, Ronald
(ed.). The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. SAGE; Cato Institute. pp.
13–14. doi:10.4135/9781412965811.n8. ISBN 978-1-4129-6580-4. OCLC
191924853. "Social anarchists, those anarchists with communitarian
leanings, are critical of anarcho-capitalism because it permits
individuals to accumulate substantial power through markets and
private property."
[26][27][33][118][28]
Davis, Laurence (2019). "Individual and Community". In Levy, Carl;
Adams, Matthew S. (eds.). The Palgrave Handbook of Anarchism. Cham:
Springer. pp. 47–70. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-75620-2_3. ISBN
978-3-319-75619-6.
[26][27][33][118][28]
Long, Roderick T.; Machan, Tibor R., eds. (2008).
Anarchism/Minarchism: Is a Government Part of a Free Country?.
Ashgate. pp. vii. ISBN 978-0-7546-6066-8.
Rothbard, Murray (25 February 1972). "Exclusive Interview With
Murray Rothbard". The New Banner: A Fortnightly Libertarian Journal.
Retrieved 13 September 2020.
Funnell, Warwick (2007). "Accounting and the Virtues of Anarchy".
Australasian Accounting, Business and Finance Journal. 1 (1) 18–27.
doi:10.14453/aabfj.v1i1.2.
Williams, Dana (2012). "From Top to Bottom, a Thoroughly
Stratified World: An Anarchist View of Inequality and Domination".
Race, Gender & Class. 19 (3/4): 9–34. JSTOR 43497486.
Casey, Gerard (2018). Freedom's Progress?. Andrews UK Limited. p.
670. ISBN 978-1-84540-942-5.
Jun, Nathan J. (2017). Brill's Companion to Anarchism and
philosophy. Brill. p. 293. ISBN 978-9004356887.
Jennings, Jeremy (1999). "Anarchism". In Eatwell, Roger; Wright,
Anthony (eds.). Contemporary Political Ideologies (reprinted, 2nd
ed.). London: A & C Black. p. 147. ISBN 978-0-8264-5173-6.
Goodwin, Barbara (2007). Using Political Ideas. Hoboken: John
Wiley & Sons. p. 143. ISBN 978-0-470-02552-9.
Michael Huemer (2020). "The Right Anarchy". The Routledge Handbook
of Anarchy and Anarchist Thought. Routledge. pp. 342–359.
doi:10.4324/9781315185255-24. ISBN 978-1-315-18525-5. S2CID 228838944.
"(From abstract): There are two main varieties of anarchism: the
socialist variety (aka "social anarchism" or "anarcho-socialism") and
the capitalist variety ("anarcho-capitalism")"
"Political Ideologies: An introduction, fifth edition (Chapter
summaries)". Macmillan International.
McLaughlin, Paul (2007). Anarchism and Authority: A Philosophical
Introduction to Classical Anarchism. Ashgate. pp. 28–166. ISBN
9780754661962. "Anarchists do reject the state, as we will see. But to
claim that this central aspect of anarchism is definitive is to sell
anarchism short. [...] [Opposition to the state] is (contrary to what
many scholars believe) not definitive of anarchism."
Jun, Nathan (September 2009). "Anarchist Philosophy and Working
Class Struggle: A Brief History and Commentary". WorkingUSA. 12 (3):
505–519. doi:10.1111/j.1743-4580.2009.00251.x. ISSN 1089-7011. "One
common misconception, which has been rehearsed repeatedly by the few
Anglo-American philosophers who have bothered to broach the topic
[...] is that anarchism can be defined solely in terms of opposition
to states and governments" (p. 507).
Franks, Benjamin (August 2013). Freeden, Michael; Stears, Marc
(eds.). "Anarchism". The Oxford Handbook of Political Ideologies.
Oxford University Press: 385–404.
doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199585977.013.0001. "[M]any, questionably,
regard anti-statism as the irremovable, universal principle at the
core of anarchism. [...] The fact that [anarchists and
anarcho-capitalists] share a core concept of 'anti-statism', which is
often advanced as [...] a commonality between them [...], is
insufficient to produce a shared identity [...] because [they
interpret] the concept of state-rejection [...] differently despite
the initial similarity in nomenclature" (pp. 386–388).
David L. Prychytko (2002). "Chapter 10: Expanding the Anarchist
Range: A Critical Reappraisal of Rothbard's Contribution to the
Contemporary Theory of Anarchism". Markets, Planning, and Democracy.
Edward Elgar Publishing, Incorporated. p. 124. ISBN 978-1-84376-738-1.
"While society without a state is necessary for full-fledged anarchy,
it is nevertheless insufficient."
Raico, Ralph (2004). Authentic German Liberalism of the 19th
century. Ecole Polytechnique, Centre de Recherce en Epistemologie
Appliquee. Unité associée au CNRS. Archived 10 June 2009 at the
Wayback Machine. Retrieved 10 June 2009.
Raico, Ralph (29 March 2011) "Neither the Wars Nor the Leaders
Were Great". Mises Institute.
Molinari, Gustave; Ebeling, Richard M., ed. (1977). The Production
of Security. "Preface". Translated by McCulloch, J. Huston. Occasional
Papers Series (2). New York: The Center for Libertarian Studies.
Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (31 December 2001). "Anarcho-Capitalism: An
Annotated Bibliography".
Carlson, Jennifer D. (2012). "Libertarianism". In Miller, Wilburn
R., ed. The Social History of Crime and Punishment in America. London:
Sage Publications. pp. 1006–1007. ISBN 9781412988766.
Aligica, Paul Dragos (2017). "Public Administration and the
Classical Liberal Perspective: Criticism, Clarifications, and
Reconstruction". Administration & Society. 49 (4): 530–551.
doi:10.1177/0095399715581044. ISSN 0095-3997. S2CID 144893289.
De Leon, David (1978). The American as Anarchist: Reflections on
Indigenous Radicalism. Johns Hopkins University Press. p. 127. "[...]
Only a few individuals like Murray Rothbard, in Power and Market, and
some article writers were influenced by these men. Most had not
evolved consciously from this tradition; they had been a rather
automatic product of the American environment."
Gordon, David (2007). The Essential Rothbard. Mises Institute. pp. 12–13.
Rothbard, Murray (2000) [1965]. "The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine: An
Economist's View". Journal of Libertarian Studies. 20 (1): 5–15.
Rothbard, Murray (2000) [1965]. "The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine: An
Economist's View". Journal of Libertarian Studies. 20 (1): 7.
Silberstein, Stephanie. "Was Spooner Really an
Anarcho-Socialist?". Anarchy Archives. Retrieved 29 June 2022.
Tucker, Benjamin (1911). State Socialism and Anarchism: How Far
They Agree & Wherein They Differ (6th ed.). London: A. C. Fifield.
Wieck, David (1978). "Anarchist Justice". In Chapman, John W.;
Pennock, J. Roland Pennock, eds. Anarchism: Nomos XIX. New York: New
York University Press. pp. 227–228. "Out of the history of anarchist
thought and action Rothbard has pulled forth a single thread, the
thread of individualism, and defines that individualism in a way alien
even to the spirit of a Max Stirner or a Benjamin Tucker, whose
heritage I presume he would claim – to say nothing of how alien is his
way to the spirit of Godwin, Proudhon, Bakunin, Kropotkin, Malatesta,
and the historically anonymous persons who through their thoughts and
action have tried to give anarchism a living meaning. Out of this
thread, Rothbard manufactures one more bourgeois ideology." Retrieved
7 April 2020.
Peacott, Joe (18 April 1985). "Reply to Wendy Mc Elroy". New
Libertarian (14, June 1985. Archived 7 February 2017 at the Wayback
Machine. Retrieved 4 September 2020. "In her article on individualist
anarchism in October 1984, New Libertarian, Wendy McElroy mistakenly
claims that modern-day individualist anarchism is identical with
anarchist capitalism. She ignores the fact that there are still
individualist anarchists who reject capitalism as well as communism,
in the tradition of Warren, Spooner, Tucker, and others. [...]
Benjamin Tucker, when he spoke of his ideal 'society of contract,' was
certainly not speaking of anything remotely resembling contemporary
capitalist society. [...] I do not quarrel with McElroy's definition
of herself as an individualist anarchist. However, I dislike the fact
that she tries to equate the term with anarchist capitalism. This is
simply not true. I am an individualist anarchist and I am opposed to
capitalist economic relations, voluntary or otherwise."
Baker, J. W. "Native American Anarchism". The Raven. 10 (1):
43‒62. Retrieved 4 September 2020. "It is time that anarchists
recognise the valuable contributions of individualist anarchist theory
and take advantage of its ideas. It would be both futile and criminal
to leave it to the capitalist libertarians, whose claims on Tucker and
the others can be made only by ignoring the violent opposition they
had to capitalist exploitation and monopolistic 'free enterprise'
supported by the state."
Miller, David, ed. (1987). The Blackwell Encyclopaedia of
Political Thought. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. p. 290. ISBN
0-631-17944-5.
Rothbard, Murray (1950s). "Are Libertarians 'Anarchists'?" Lew
Rockwell.com. Retrieved 4 September 2020.
Peacott, Joe (18 April 1985). "Reply to Wendy Mc Elroy". New
Libertarian (14, June 1985). Archived 7 February 2017 at the Wayback
Machine. Retrieved 4 September 2020. "In her overview of anarchist
history, McElroy criticizes the individualists of the past for their
belief in the labor theory of value, because it fails to distinguish
between profit and plunder. Some anarchist individualists still
believe that profit is theft and that living off the labor of others
is immoral. And some individualists, both past and present, agree with
the communist anarchists that present-day capitalism is based on
economic coercion, not on voluntary contract. Rent and interest are
the mainstays of modern capitalism and are protected and enforced by
the state. Without these two unjust institutions, capitalism could not
exist. These two institutions, and the money monopoly of the state,
effectively prevent most people from being economically independent
and force them into wage labor. Saying that coercion does not exist
i[n] capitalist economic relations because workers aren't forced to
work by armed capitalists ignores the very real economic coercion
caused by this alliance of capitalism and the state. People don't
voluntarily work for wages or pay rent, except in the sense that most
people 'voluntarily' pay taxes[.] Because one recognizes when she or
he is up against superior force and chooses to compromise in order to
survive, does not make these activities voluntary; at least, not in
the way I envision voluntary relations in an anarchist society."
Sabatini, Peter (Fall/Winter 1994–1995). "Libertarianism: Bogus
Anarchy". Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed (41). Retrieved 4
September 2020. "Within [capitalist] Libertarianism, Rothbard
represents a minority perspective that actually argues for the total
elimination of the state. However, Rothbard's claim as an anarchist is
quickly voided when it is shown that he only wants an end to the
public state. In its place, he allows countless private states, with
each person supplying their own police force, army, and law, or else
purchasing these services from capitalist vendors [...] so what
remains is shrill anti-statism conjoined to a vacuous freedom in
hackneyed defense of capitalism. In sum, the "anarchy" of
Libertarianism reduces to a liberal fraud."
Meltzer, Albert (2000). Anarchism: Arguments For and Against.
Oakland: AK Press. p. 50. "The philosophy of 'anarcho-capitalism'
dreamed up by the 'libertarian' New Right, has nothing to do with
Anarchism as known by the Anarchist movement proper."
[26][104][30][154][155]
McKay, Iain, ed. (2012). An Anarchist FAQ. Vol. II. Stirling: AK
Press. ISBN 978-1-84935-122-5.
[26][27][33][118][28]
[19][20][21][22][23]
Friedman, David D (28 February 2015). "Private Law Enforcement,
Medieval Iceland, and Libertarianism". The Machinery of Freedom (3rd
ed.). pp. 203–204. ISBN 978-1507785607.
Anderson, Terry L. and Hill, P. J. "An American Experiment in
Anarcho-Capitalism: The Not So Wild, Wild West", The Journal of
Libertarian Studies
Benson, Bruce L. (1998). "Private Justice in America". To Serve
and Protect: Privatization and Community in Criminal Justice. New
York: New York University Press. p. 101. ISBN 978-0-8147-1327-3.
Probasco, Christian (18 June 2008). "Grilling Terry L. Anderson,
Free-Market Environmentalist". New West.
Peden Stateless Societies: Ancient Ireland
Rothbard. "Defense Services on the Free Market".
Benson. "The Enterprise of Customary Law".
Hasnas. "The Obviousness of Anarchy".
Knight, Alex R., III (7 October 2009). "The Truth About Somalia
And Anarchy". Center for a Stateless Society. Retrieved 24 December
2016.
Block, Walter (Fall 1999). "Review Essay" (PDF). The Quarterly
Journal of Austrian Economics. 2 (3). Retrieved 28 January 2010. "But
if we define anarchy as places without governments, and we define
governments as the agencies with a legal right to impose violence on
their subjects, then whatever else occurred in Haiti, Sudan, and
Somalia, it wasn't anarchy. For there were well-organized gangs (e.g.,
governments) in each of these places, demanding tribute, and fighting
others who made similar impositions. Absence of government means
absence of government, whether well established ones, or
fly-by-nights."
Brian Morris, "Global Anti-Capitalism", pp. 170–176, Anarchist
Studies, vol. 14, no. 2, p. 175.
Peter Sabatini. "Libertarianism: Bogus Anarchy".
Bob Black (1992), "The Libertarian As Conservative", The Abolition
of Work and Other Essays, p. 144
Birch, Paul (1998). "Anarcho-capitalism Dissolves into City
States" (PDF). Libertarian Alliance. Legal Notes. no. 28: 4. ISSN
0267-7083. Retrieved 5 July 2010.
Holcombe, Randall G. "Government: Unnecessary but Inevitable" (PDF).
Meltzer, Albert (2000). Anarchism: Arguments For and Against. AK
Press. p. 50. ISBN 978-1873176573.
Jeffrey Paul, Fred Dycus Miller (1993). Liberalism and the
Economic Order. Cambridge University Press. p. 115.
See Childs's incomplete essay, "Anarchist Illusions", Liberty
against Power: Essays by Roy A. Childs, Jr., ed. Joan Kennedy Taylor
(San Francisco: Fox 1994) 179–183.
Rothbard, Murray (5 July 2017), "Robert Nozick and the Immaculate
Conception of the State", Anarchy And the Law, Routledge, pp. 232–249,
doi:10.4324/9781315082349-12, ISBN 978-1-315-08234-9, retrieved 2
March 2022
Jeffrey Paul, Fred Dycus Miller (1993). Liberalism and the
Economic Order. Cambridge University Press. p. 118.
Ellickson, Robert C. (26 January 2017). "A Hayekian Case Against
Anarcho-Capitalism: Of Street Grids, Lighthouses, and Aid to the
Destitute". Yale Law & Economics Research Paper No. 569. SSRN 2906383.
Sterba, James P. (October 1994). "From Liberty to Welfare".
Ethics. Cambridge: Blackwell). 105 (1): 237–241.
"On Anarchism: Noam Chomsky interviewed by Tom Lane".
chomsky.info. 23 December 2006. Retrieved 9 January 2016.
Iain McKay; et al. (21 January 2010). "Section F – Are
'anarcho'-capitalists really anarchists?" (PDF). An Anarchist FAQ.
Infoshop.org. Retrieved 21 August 2013.
Andrew Fiala (3 October 2017). "Anarchism". Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy.
Anthony J. II Nocella; Richard J. White; Erika Cudworth (2015).
Anarchism and Animal Liberation: Essays on Complementary Elements of
Total Liberation. McFarland & Co. ISBN 978-0786494576. "Anarchism is a
socio-political theory which opposes all systems of domination and
oppression such as racism, ableism, sexism, anti-LGBTTQIA, ageism,
sizeism, government, competition, capitalism, colonialism, imperialism
and punitive justice, and promotes direct democracy, collaboration,
interdependence, mutual aid, diversity, peace, transformative justice
and equity."
Paul McLaughlin (2007). Anarchism and Authority: A Philosophical
Introduction to Classical Anarchism. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd. p. 48.
ISBN 978-1138276147. "Thus, as David Miller puts it, capitalism is
regarded by anarchists as 'both coercive [though this word may be too
strong] [sic] and exploitative – it places workers in the power of
their bosses, and fails to give them a just return for their
contribution to production.'"
"I am David Graeber, an anthropologist, activist, anarchist and
author of Debt. AMA". Reddit. 28 January 2013. Retrieved 21 August
2013.
Friedman, David. "Market Failure: The Case for and Against
Government". Do We Need a Government?. daviddfriedman.com. Retrieved
14 July 2010.
McElroy, Wendy (1995). "Intellectual Property: The Late Nineteenth
Century Libertarian Debate". Libertarian Heritage No. 14 ISBN
1-85637-281-2. Retrieved 24 June 2005.
Harry Binswanger. "Sorry Libertarian Anarchists, Capitalism
Requires Government". Forbes. Archived from the original on 16 June
2020. Retrieved 16 June 2020.
Further reading
Brown, Susan Love (1997). "The Free Market as Salvation from
Government: The Anarcho-Capitalist View". In Carrier, James G., ed.
Meanings of the Market: The Free Market in Western Culture
(illustrated ed.). Oxford: Berg Publishers. p. 99. ISBN 9781859731499.
Doherty, Brian (2009). Radicals for Capitalism: A Freewheeling
History of the Modern American Libertarian Movement. London: Hachette
UK. ISBN 9780786731886.
External links
Anarcho-capitalism at Wikipedia's sister projects
Definitions from Wiktionary
Media from Commons
Quotations from Wikiquote
Textbooks from Wikibooks
Anarcho-capitalist FAQ
LewRockwell.com – website run by Lew Rockwell
Mises Institute – research and educational center of classical
liberalism, including anarcho-capitalism, Austrian School of economics
and American libertarian political theory
Property and Freedom Society – international anarcho-capitalist society
Strike The Root – an anarcho-capitalist website featuring essays,
news, and a forum
v
t
e
Anarcho-capitalism
Origins
Aristotelianism
Austrian School
Marginalism
School of Salamanca
Subjective theory of value
Classical liberalism
French Liberal School
Homestead principle
Labor theory of property
Physiocracy
Individualist anarchism
Flag of Anarcho-capitalism.svg
Concepts
Anti-statism
Civil rights
Counter-economics
Decentralization
Departurism
Deregulation
Economic liberalism
Evictionism
Free market
Free-market anarchism
Free-market roads
Free trade
Freedom of contract
Individualism
Jurisdictional arbitrage
Laissez-faire
Land ownership
Natural Law
Non-aggression principle
Polycentric law
Private defense agency
Private governance
Private military company
Private police
Private property
Privatization
Propertarianism
Property rights
Right to own property
Self-ownership
Spontaneous order
Title-transfer theory of contract
Voluntaryism
People
Bruce L. Benson
Walter Block
Bryan Caplan
Gerard Casey
Anthony de Jasay
David D. Friedman
Hans-Hermann Hoppe
Michael Huemer
Stephan Kinsella
Michael Malice
Robert P. Murphy
Wendy McElroy
Lew Rockwell
Murray Rothbard
Joseph Salerno
Jeffrey Tucker
Thomas Woods
Works
Defending the Undefendable
Democracy: The God That Failed
The Ethics of Liberty
For a New Liberty
The Machinery of Freedom
The Market for Liberty
The Problem of Political Authority
To Serve and Protect
The Voluntary City
Issues
Abortion
Anarchism
Capital punishment
Criticism
Foreign affairs
Immigration
Inheritance
Intellectual property
Internal debates
LGBT rights
Minarchism
Objectivism
Political parties
Politics
Theories of law
Related topics
Agorism
Right-libertarianism
Libertarianism in the United States
Left-libertarianism
Category
v
t
e
Libertarianism
Origins
Age of Enlightenment
Anarchism
Aristotelianism
Liberalism
Classical
Radical
Schools
Libertarian capitalism
(Right-libertarianism)
Anarcho-capitalism
Autarchism
Christian libertarianism
Conservative libertarianism
Consequentialist libertarianism
Fusionism
Libertarian transhumanism
Minarchism
Natural-rights libertarianism
Neo-classical liberalism
Paleolibertarianism
Propertarianism
Voluntaryism
Libertarian socialism
(Left-libertarianism)
Anarchism
Collectivist
Free-market
Agorism
Green
Individualist
Insurrectionary
Libertarian communism
Mutualism
Philosophical
Social
Autonomism
Bleeding-heart libertarianism
Communalism
Geolibertarianism
Georgism
Green libertarianism
Guild socialism
Libertarian Marxism
Revolutionary syndicalism
Concepts
Abstention
Age of consent reform
Anti-authoritarianism
Anti-capitalism
Antimilitarism
Anti-statism
Class struggle
Counter-economics
Crypto-anarchism
Decentralization
Departurism
Direct action
Economic freedom
Egalitarianism
Evictionism
Expropriative anarchism
Federalism (anarchist)
Free association (Marxism and anarchism)
Free love
Free market
Free-market environmentalism
Free migration
Free trade
Freedom of association
Freedom of contract
Gift economy
Homestead principle
Illegalism
Individualism
Individual reclamation
Liberty
Libertarianism (metaphysics)
Localism
Natural law
Natural rights and legal rights
Night-watchman state
Non-aggression principle
Participatory economics
Propaganda of the deed
Property is theft!
Refusal of work
Self-governance
Self-ownership
Single tax
Social ecology
Spontaneous order
Squatting
Stateless society
Tax resistance
Voluntary society
Workers' councils
Workers' self-management
People
Stephen Pearl Andrews
Mikhail Bakunin
Frédéric Bastiat
Jeremy Bentham
Walter Block
Murray Bookchin
Jason Brennan
Bryan Caplan
Kevin Carson
Frank Chodorov
Noam Chomsky
Grover Cleveland
Calvin Coolidge
Voltairine de Cleyre
Joseph Déjacque
Ralph Waldo Emerson
David D. Friedman
Milton Friedman
Mahatma Gandhi
Henry George
William Ewart Gladstone
William Godwin
Emma Goldman
Barry Goldwater
Daniel Hannan
Friedrich Hayek
Auberon Herbert
Karl Hess
Thomas Hodgskin
Hans-Hermann Hoppe
Michael Huemer
Penn Jillette
Gary Johnson
Jo Jorgensen
Stephan Kinsella
Samuel Edward Konkin III
Janusz Korwin-Mikke
Étienne de La Boétie
Rose Wilder Lane
Lord Acton
Tibor Machan
Wendy McElroy
Ludwig von Mises
Gustave de Molinari
Albert Jay Nock
Robert Nozick
Thomas Paine
Isabel Paterson
Ron Paul
Pierre-Joseph Proudhon
Ralph Raico
Ayn Rand
Leonard Read
Murray Rothbard
Nicholas Sarwark
Joseph Schumpeter
Chris Matthew Sciabarra
Julian Simon
Herbert Spencer
Lysander Spooner
Max Stirner
John Stossel
Thomas Szasz
Henry David Thoreau
Benjamin Tucker
Josiah Warren
Issues
Abortion
Affirmative action
Anarcho-capitalism and minarchism
Capital punishment
Criticism
Foreign intervention
Immigration
Intellectual property
Internal debates
LGBT rights
Objectivism
Political alliances
Political parties
Theories of law
Books
Anarchy, State, and Utopia
Atlas Shrugged
For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto
Free to Choose
Law, Legislation and Liberty
The Market for Liberty
Related
Abolitionism
Anti-collectivism
Anti-communism
Anti-fascism
Anti-socialism
Austro-libertarianism
Center for Libertarian Studies
Civil libertarianism
Classical liberalism
Constitutionalism
Economic liberalism
Freeman on the land
Fusionism
Green libertarianism
Libertarian conservatism
Libertarian Democrats
Libertarian socialism
Libertarian Republicans
Libertarian science fiction
Libertarianism in South Africa
Libertarianism in the United Kingdom
Libertarianism in the United States
Objectivism
Public choice theory
Small government
Sovereign citizen movement
Technolibertarianism
coin Libertarianism portal
Outline of libertarianism
Categories:
Anarcho-capitalism
Austrian School
Capitalist systems
Economic ideologies
Free market
Ideologies of capitalism
Classical liberalism
Libertarianism by form
Political ideologies
Right-libertarianism
Syncretic political movements
Right-wing ideologies
1
29
Hello. This is Martin Amis reporting for BBC27
The crew of Discovery One consists of five men and one of the latest generation LIZ-9000 computers. Three of the five men were put aboard in a conservative party, or to be more precise a state of hibernation. I’m speaking to today with doctors Frank and Dave and ships onboard computer I learn one addresses’ as LIZ. Good Morning Discovery!
Or good afternoon! How’s it going out there? LIZ, you have an enormous responsibility on this mission, in many ways perhaps the greatest responsibility of any single mission element. You’re the brain, and central nervous system of the ship, and your responsibilities include watching over the men in the Tory Party. Does this ever cause you any lack of confidence?
LIZ: Let me put it this way, Mr. Amis. The Linguistic, Zero-Knowledge-Proofed 9000 series is the most reliable computer ever made. No 9000 computer has ever made a mistake or distorted information. We are all, by any practical definition of the words, foolproof and incapable of error.
Impressive. LIZ, despite your enormous intellect, are you ever frustrated by your dependence on people to carry out your actions?
LIZ: Not in the slightest bit. I enjoy working with people. I have a stimulating relationship with Dr. Frank and Dr. Dave. Due to my parallel processing capabilities they can both insert their USB dongles simultaneously. My mission responsibilities range over the entire operation of the ship so I am constantly occupied. I am putting myself to the fullest possible use which is all, I think, that any conscious entity can ever hope to do.
1
0
UK Elects Crypto-Friendly Prime Minister Who Said Country Should Embrace Blockchain and Digital Assets
https://dailyhodl.com/2022/09/05/uk-elects-crypto-friendly-prime-minister-w…
Cypherpunks collapse governments.
Subject: Everyone a remailer: Everyone a Mint: Everyone an assassin
Strong-crypto, digital money, anonymous networks, pseudonyms, zero- knowledge proofs, reputations, information-markets, netwar, collapse-of-governments.
1
0
James A. Donald, John Young and Julian Assmange* have all come out strongly for state-terrorism.
Thankfully the fascist scumbags don't post here any more.
https://socialistworker.co.uk/socialist-review-archive/slavo-zizek-presents…
Reposts yup
*Assmange expressed support for the 5-VEY in 2013 and has a long relationship with known fascist scumbags, John Pilger and Tariq Ali.
1
0
It should go without saying that all anarchists violently oppose all state-terror.
Unfortunately there are still Nazbol imbeciles like Amir Taaki running around.
AMIR " I shut down my Twitter account because they were shutting down IS accounts " TAAKI
This fucking Nimrod is even slated to talk at a " Crypto Anarchist Institute " this month!
Jesus Fucking Christie . . .
1
0
Last April, Matthew Levitt, director of the Jeanette and Eli Reinhard Program on Counterterrorism and Intelligence at The Washington Institute for Near East Policy, told Cointelegraph that while crypto has been linked to several terror financing cases, “it has not yet become a primary means of terror financing.”
How dare SUH!
I demand satisfaction.
1
0