[header.gif] Volume 21, Number 2 December 1999 __________________________________________________________________ Kant vs. Locke on the Right to Rebel by Daniel O'Connor In his essay "Theory and Practice," Immanuel Kant argues that citizens must always obey their government and consequently never rebel against it. He defends this absolute prohibition by claiming that rebellion would violate requirements of duty and morality, [1]1 which theoretically permit only a government to interpret the moral will of a society and obligate citizens to act according only to a priori reason. Despite Kant's objections, Locke's principles of rebellion not only conform to the Kantian categorical imperative and support the right of a collective to determine and execute rebellion for itself, but also demonstrate paradoxes that in general trouble Kantian political theory. Kant bases his political theory on the morality that he develops in the Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. Fundamentally, Kant claims that the basis of morality is a good will that acts only according to a conception of Pure Duty, duty that "help[s] others where one can . . . [with an] inclination for the sake of duty alone." [2]2 Kant argues that a priori reason compels one to act according to such a conception of duty. [3]3 Thus, Kant defines duty as "the necessity to act out of reverence for the [universal] law." [4]4 Thus, only actions consistent with the categorical imperative are moral. [5]5 Kant then derives two important formulations of the categorical imperative. These are the Formula of the End in Itself, [6]6 and the Formula of the Kingdom of Ends. [7]7 When a citizenry upholds the "Kingdom of Ends" by willing laws according to the categorical imperative, it also wills the government's implementation of those laws. [8]8 Thus, as Kant argues in "Theory and Practice," when a government implements the moral will, the citizenry must comply with even unpleasant actions. Pure reason alone, not the happiness of the citizenry, generates the categorical imperative. [9]9 From this, Kant discovers an absolute prohibition on resistance because, he claims, resistance universalizes only anarchy, [10]10 not the Kingdom of Ends. [11]11 Resistance hinders the implementation of the society's moral will, thus creating a contradiction. [12]12 Kant also argues that only the "supreme arbiter of public right," even if he is a tyrant, can interpret and implement the moral law; thus, rebellion of the people could never constitute a legitimate execution of the moral will. [13]13 Finally, any coercion or force involved with the rebellion would involve brutality, which only "perpetrate[s] . . . wrong[s] of the highest degree." [14]14 John Locke's opposing stance on the right to revolt can help to highlight some of the problems in the Kantian view. Like Kant, Locke argues that society fundamentally values "reason." [15]15 However, Locke argues that reason compels citizens principally to value property [16]16 and to create government to help them protect this property. [17]17 Consequently, once a government fails to protect, or, worse yet, harms, the citizens' property, that government "dissolves" its right to legitimately rule the people, giving right to the collective to establish a new government. [18]18 Locke argues that only a "long train of abuses," such as the use of tyrannical and capricious power against the collective, enslavement, and arbitrary rule without regard to the moral will justifies such a revolt against the government. [19]19 The categorical imperative may indeed uphold Kant's absolute prohibition on rebellion. Paradoxically, the categorical imperative also seems to support Lockean justifications for rebellion. First, and most importantly, Locke's conception of rebellion seems consistent with Kant's conception of duty. As mentioned above, even Kant can conceive of the possibility of a ruler tyrannizing the collective moral will. [20]20 An evil tyrant could arbitrarily murder innocent citizens or commit other moral atrocities against the collective and forbid citizens to oppose these actions. Kant argues that pure moral action is action solely based on the idea of duty. It would seem, then, that, in this scenario, citizens would be morally obligated to violate and resist the law and assume their duty to save these citizens from harm. Thus, the universal maxim that a citizen must always help another individual facing imminent harm justifies resistance to a state that uses unjust force against its citizens. Similarly, a government that coerces its citizens to act unwillingly would violate the Autonomy Principle. Any government [21]21 that prevents any citizen from determining and acting upon universal maxims of morality would not respect the individual's ability to will the categorical imperative. This is a violation of the Autonomy Formulation of the categorical imperative. Any Kantian collective striving to achieve moral freedom would be thus morally obligated to resist all forms of external enslavement. Thus, the Autonomy Formulation universalizes the Lockean principle of resistance to a government that enslaves its people. [22]22 Finally, the Kingdom of Ends also seems to universalize resistance. If the Kingdom of Ends requires government to execute and protect the moral will, any government that neglects its duties, fails to implement the moral will, rules without regard to the moral will, or arbitrarily alters the government, violates the categorical imperative. [23]23 In these cases, [24]24 the government would deliberately stop administering the moral will, thus challenging the enforcement, legitimacy, and perhaps even the existence [25]25 of the moral will. Thus, any Kantian society would be morally obligated to ignore a government that neglected its duties and to establish a new government that would do its job. Thus, the Kingdom of Ends universalizes Lockean principles of resistance when the government neglects its duty. Consequently, the only legitimate government in a Kantian sense is a government that adheres to and implements the collective moral will. As I have just shown, when a government attempts to destroy the moral will, denies its citizens the ability to create the moral will, or neglects the moral will (thus preventing the moral will from actualizing itself), the government violates the categorical imperative. Therefore, the categorical imperative universalizes the notion that these forms of government are illegitimate. When a government violates the categorical imperative, the government "dissolves" its legitimate claim to govern. [26]26 As Locke rightly points out, such an illegitimate government is the true rebel force, since it imposes its own will upon the collective, rather than merely implementing the collective moral will, thus "rebelling" against its duty to enforce the collective moral will. [27]27 Consequently, Kantian citizens have an obligation to restore legitimate rule not only because legitimate rule alone conforms to the categorical imperative, but also because they have a duty to the collective to protect and uphold the moral will. Moreover, if the collective wills the government in the first place, then the collective should have the ability to will another government when the first government fails to uphold the collective's values. Consequently, there are also many responses to Kant's argument that rebellion requires immoral actions in order to accomplish its purposes. Most importantly, Locke responds with the idea of supreme necessity: in extreme circumstances, a citizen must protect one's own life and the lives of one's fellow citizens. Violence to reinstate a moral government would be a lesser evil than permitting an evil government to reign. A tyranny [28]28 that destroys the moral innocence of the collective that it is supposed to represent causes far greater, more insidious and more irreparable evils than does the violence that attempts to remedy it. [29]29 Besides, if the categorical imperative justifies rebellion, then the categorical imperative also justifies the means to accomplish this rebellion. Finally, as Locke observes, "this doctrine of a power in the people of providing for their safety a-new . . . is the best fence against rebellion" because a government that respects the collective's ability to form a new government is a government that understands the limits of its own power. [30]30 Kant's problems concerning rebellion demonstrate serious flaws in Kantian political theory. First, the categorical imperative leads ironically to moral relativism, not moral absolutism. Both Kant and Locke base their political theory upon the idea of "reason." However, Kant and Locke generate radically different conceptions of reason, one based on a priori reason, the other on self-preservation. Both Kant and Locke use "reason" to justify their very different views on the political right to rebel. The categorical imperative, instead of supporting one idea and disproving its opposite, seems paradoxically to support both. Can an absolute principle still be absolute if its contradiction is also absolute? If the categorical imperative can generate both a principle and its antithesis, then can't the categorical imperative generate any principle? [31]31 Kant assumes that since a priori reason generates universal principles, everyone will generate the same precepts and act similarly in similar circumstances. Since people reason differently, and since the categorical imperative seems to derive whatever an individual wants it to, the categorical imperative seems to support moral relativism, rather than moral absolutism. Thus, a government that bases itself upon the moral will of the collective would found itself on relativist principles, thereby annihilating the ability of its citizens to unite. In addition, Kant's notions of individual rights conflict with his notions of legitimate state power. The categorical imperative aims to empower individual rights over the state, while simultaneously creating and giving legitimacy to the state. Then Kant argues that when the state forms, the collective must always obey the government--in effect, arguing that the state becomes more important than the individuals that willed its existence. The system works as long as the government reflects the collective's moral will, because then it remains impossible to determine whether the collective or the government has control. However, if an evil regime controls the government and works contrary to the moral will, Kant argues that the state still has supremacy. In such circumstances, Kant should have argued that individual members of the collective have a duty to achieve moral freedom beyond any requirements of governments. Then he would have discovered that individual members of the collective always have a duty to resist and rebel, to strive for moral freedom. Consequently, Kant should have discovered that the moral needs of the individual citizens should always outweigh the needs of the state. The failure of Kantian logic to defend against Locke's qualifications for rebellion demonstrates weaknesses in Kantian political thought. Since the categorical imperative generates both an absolute prohibition against rebellion as well as exceptions to this absolute prohibition, a collective ought to expect the categorical imperative to derive only relative, not absolute, morality. Kantian limitations on the freedoms of the collective also contradict the moral needs and requirements of the collective. As a result, it seems impossible for a society to adhere to Kantian conceptions of reason and morality and still conform to a Kantian conception of government. Besides, a bitter irony seems to exist suggesting that a moral people would never want to live in a Kantian society. If morality to Kant means compliance with the law even during the darkest times, a moral people could violate laws of duty to maintain personal moral purity, thus committing greater, more morally haunting, sins of inaction in time of greatest need. Great intentions have created marvelous wonders in the world. Yet, even these great intentions, when unchecked, have and will continue to cause far greater moral disasters than those they purport to help. Indeed, we live in a world "where to do harm/Is often laudable, to do good sometime/[is] dangerous folly." [32]32 Endnotes _____________________ ^1 Kant describes both duty and the categorical imperative in great detail in his Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. ^2 Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. Trans. H.J. Paton (New York: Harper & Row Publications, 1964), 66. ^3 Ibid., 68. ^4 Ibid., 68. ^5 The categorical imperative is: "Act as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature." Ibid., 70. Kant also refers to this as the "Formula of the Universal Law." Ibid., 88. ^6 Also known as the Law of Autonomy. Ibid., 98. ^7 "A rational being must always be regarded as making universal law." Ibid., 102. ^8 Immanuel Kant, "On the Proverb: That May be True in Theory, But is of No Practical Use." Perpetual Peace and other Essays. Trans.Ted Humphrey. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983), 79. ^9 "[Kant] will only note that in discussions of right its source is the common fallacy of substituting the principle of happiness for the principle of right" Ibid., 81. ^10 Kant would likely define anarchy as picking which laws to obey and which laws to disobey, based on a conception of personal happiness. ^11 Ibid. ^12 "Such resistance would have to derive from a maxim that, if made universal, would destroy all civil constitutions, thus annihilating the only state in which men can possess rights." Ibid. ^13 "Only he who is the supreme arbiter of public right can do so- and that that is precisely the nation's leader. Thus no one in the commonwealth can have a right to challenge that authority" Ibid., 80. ^14 "Even where one grants that no wrong is done to a prince . . . by such an uprising" Ibid. ^15 John Locke. Second Treatise of Government. ed. C.B. Macpherson. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1980). "Are the people to be blamed, if they have the sense of rational creatures . . . ?" §230. ^16 Life, liberty, and fortunes. Ibid., §221 (but referred to throughout the entire Treatise). ^17 Ibid., §111 " . . . men found it necessary to examine more carefully the original and rights government, and to find out ways to restrain the exorbitances, and prevent the abuses of that power, which they having intrusted in another's hands only for their own good . . . " ^18 Ibid., §205. ^19Ibid 18. §210. " . . . a long train of actions shew the councils all tend that way . . . " toward rebellion. ^20 Ibid 18. §207-§209. ^21 The situation would be worse if the government enslaves its citizens and forces them to commit immoral actions for immoral purposes. Regardless, even a benevolent condition of servitude that achieves moral ends violates the categorical imperative. ^22 Ibid., §222 ^23 Ibid., §214-§220. ^24 The first two cases suggest that the government works towards the destruction of the moral will, or otherwise violates it. In this case, the moral will, at least in its collective sense, seems to still exist (see the following note). ^25 It would seem that from a people moral because they accept their duty, someone would realize that they had a duty to enforce the moral will. Thus, if no one feels the need to enforce the moral will, it suggests that the collective does not universalize actions because of duty, and thus does not universalize actions according to the categorical imperative. ^26 Ibid., §219 ^27 Ibid. ^28 For example, the Chinese occupation of Tibet in 1950 to the present destroyed a radically pacifist Buddhist society, necessitating Tibetan citizens to turn to violent revolts in 1954, 1987 and 1993. ^29 Ibid., § 224 and §225. ^30 Ibid., §226 ^31 Hegel, when attacking Kant in the Philosophy of History, claims that Kant "is by no means passive as regards the exercise of his thinking powers. He brings his categories with him, and sees the phenomena presented to his mental vision, exclusively through these media." Hegel perhaps suggests that Kant inserts his own personal opinions into political theory and uses the categorical imperative to "prove" its truth, rather than allowing the categorical imperative to lead him to its natural political conclusions (if there are any) (11). ^32 William Shakespeare, Macbeth in The Complete Works (New York: Gramercy Books, 1975), IV.ii.84-86. __________________________________________________________________ [33][home.gif] [34][past.gif] [35][subs.gif] [36][link.gif] [37][mboxsm.gif] [38][mission.gif] [39]Home [40]Back Issues [41]Subscribe to YPQ [42]Political Links [43]Letter to the Editor [44]YPQ's Mission Copyright 1999, The Yale Political Quarterly References 1. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn1 2. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn2 3. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn3 4. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn4 5. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn5 6. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn6 7. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn7 8. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn8 9. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn9 10. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn10 11. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn11 12. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn12 13. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn13 14. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn14 15. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn15 16. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn16 17. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn17 18. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn18 19. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn19 20. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn20 21. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn21 22. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn22 23. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn23 24. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn24 25. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn25 26. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn26 27. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn27 28. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn28 29. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn29 30. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn30 31. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn31 32. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/20001125/d5f771eb/attachment-tmp.html#fn32 33. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/index.html 34. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/pastissues.html 35. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/subscribe.html 36. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/links.html 37. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/letter.html 38. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/mission.html 39. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/index.html 40. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/pastissues.html 41. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/subscribe.html 42. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/links.html 43. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/letter.html 44. file:///var/lib/mailman/archives/private/cypherpunks-legacy/attachments/mission.html